Journal of Boredom
Studies (ISSN 2990-2525)
Issue 2, 2024, pp. 1-5
https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.10435658
https://www.boredomsociety.com/jbs
Kevin Gary: Why Boredom Matters: Education, Leisure,
and the Quest for a Meaningful Life. Cambridge University Press, 2022, pp. 146.
ISBN: 9781108878319
Mariusz Finkielsztein
Collegium Civitas
mariusz.finkielsztein@gmail.com
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1620-9402
How to cite this paper: Finkielsztein,
M. (2024). Kevin Gary: Why Boredom
Matters: Education, Leisure, and the Quest for a Meaningful Life. Cambridge University Press, 2022, pp. 146.
ISBN 9781108878319. Journal of Boredom
Studies, 2.
https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.10435658
Why Boredom Matters by Kevin Gary is a philosophical
investigation into the moral dimension of boredom and a proposal for an
antidote to it, especially in education. The starting point for Gary is the
stultifying experience of school boredom and socialization towards it that
schools produce. The author identifies two strategies that educational
institutions advocate and teach: (1) boredom avoidance— “adopting new
initiative after new initiative in the hope that boredom can be outrun
altogether” (p. 1); and (2) resignation to boredom—accepting the boring
situation as inevitable and complying with it. The combination of these two
strategies, which constitute part of schools’ hidden curriculum (an implicit or
latent message that is transmitted through education) is, as Gary rightly states,
“arguably an ideal disposition for modern worker, who needs a capacity to
endure, without complaint, hours of tedious and mindless tasks, punctuated by
weekends filled with consumptive diversions” (p. 2). The message of education
for capitalism is clear, as Gary points out: “Boredom should be, first and
foremost, avoided; if avoidance is not possible, then it should be endured as
an inevitable, albeit unpleasant, part of life” (p. 2). As a result, “we
fashion lives that are essentially guided by boredom avoidance” (p. 3) as
consumers and boredom resignation as employees. This situation is beneficial
and, more to the point, profitable for capitalists, but inhibits human
flourishing. As Gary claims, we are used to looking for remedies to our boredom
in external sources, when actually, this problem “is
rooted within the self” (p. 4)—and it should be resolved within it. Schools
should “graduate students who know how to engage boredom productively when it
arises” (p. 3), and the ultimate antidote to it, according to Gary, is teaching
true leisure as “simply avoiding boredom or helplessly blaming boredom on
something or someone else” (p. 3) does not solve the problem of situational
boredom but rather only deepens existential boredom.
The
book is logically and well-structured, with one line of reasoning. The starting
point for Gary is showing the moral significance of boredom and finding a true
remedy to the problem it poses. The author observes the ‘de-moralization’ of
boredom—it is now regarded more as a neutral state rather than a serious moral
concern. Yet, as Gary reasons, by avoiding boredom, “we are losing our moral
compass”, and boredom “negatively impacts […] our moral reasoning” (p. 5).
Essentially, the author deals primarily with existential boredom, the state of
crisis of meaning associated with the feeling of vanity about everything and
losing the will or desire to do anything, as nothing is worth pursuing. Gary
understands existential boredom more or less in the
same way as Heidegger, but his reasoning is primarily based on Kierkegaard’s
concept of sickness unto death, i.e., despair. According to this Danish
Christian philosopher, as Gary reads him, boredom is a form of despair. It is
caused by the avoidance or failure to properly synthesize the parts of the self
(body and soul). Kierkegaard distinguishes two kinds of despair: (1) despair of
infinitude/possibility—one becomes lost among uncountable and unrealizable
possibilities; this kind of despair, according to Gary, correlates with boredom
avoidance; and (2) despair of finitude/necessity—one accepts a worldly
mentality and cannot see anything beyond everyday matters; this kind correlates
with boredom resignation. Existential boredom is a form of despair and is
universal: “The key distinction is not whether or not we are in despair, but
the degree to which we are conscious of this fact or not” (p. 64). In other
words, according to Gary, everybody, to some extent, experiences existential
boredom.
To
such a universal malaise, Gary sees ‘a promising antidote’ in the practice of
leisure. Yet, what we understand and practice as leisure nowadays is not the
leisure that Gary advocates. In popular usage, leisure serves as a synonym for
rest and relaxation, the mere opposite of work, usually in the form of
amusement. Such leisure does not cure existential boredom; but, contrarily, in
the end, it intensifies it. Following Aristotle, Gary contends that true
leisure is “a state of inner tranquility that enables
the soul to greet the world receptively, in awareness of its mystery, rather
than as something to be mastered” (p. 79). In other words, it is a practice
focused on benefits inherent to the activity and not aimed at external benefits
(achievements, etc.). In our modern society, such leisure is rare, as
everything should be done for a reason (we have a “production-oriented”
conception of action [Brewer, 2009, p. 13]) and should be rationalized
by external benefits—we jog for health betterment, we read to pass the exam, we
cook to nourish ourselves, we work to be paid, etc. Gary reminds us that true
leisure, or acquiring a ‘leisurely state of mind’, requires discipline,
vigilance, and training: “Leisure is a state of mind in which we receptively
behold the world, attend to its unique sensory and spiritual offerings, and
open ourselves to be transformed by the message these have for us” (p. 84). As Gary
attempts to convince us, such leisure embraces not only creative and/or
meditative activities such as art, scientific inquiry, or sports, but also
mundane activities such as cooking or walking. True leisure is about deep
attendance (awareness of the present moment) and connection between our bodies
and minds as well as between us and others. The book concludes with a short
description of ways in which a leisurely way of being can be learnt and
cultivated.
The
book is well-written and reads well; it was definitely a
pleasure to read it. It is also nicely structured and highly disciplined in its
thinking. The discussion of Kierkegaard’s concept of despair and boredom is
invigorating, highly captivating, and well delivered. I find the author’s
thesis about the universality of existential boredom highly intriguing. I am
not certain that it is correct, as the author does not discuss it further—it
is, rather, an initial assumption provided without thorough analysis. To that
proposition, I am tempted to respond using Leopardi’s statement—as I would
always like to respond to all those who deny ever being bored—that “boredom is
felt only by those in whom the mind is of some relevance” (2015, sec. 4306)—and I am not at all convinced that
this is something so universal as despair for Kierkegaard. Nevertheless,
putting aside our opposite views on the prevalence of existential boredom, it
is an interesting contribution to the ongoing discussion. Peter Toohey (2011) claimed that existential boredom is a category whose “basis is more
intellectual than experiential” and a condition that seems “to be more read
about and discussed than actually experienced” (p. 6). However, Lars Svendsen (2016) disagrees, pointing to himself as a specimen
of existential boredom. Gary adds a new chapter to that discussion.
I have three major criticisms
of Gary’s book. The first concerns boredom, the second leisure, and the third
morality and acedia.
1. As a boredom scholar
and researcher, I find the literature review on boredom rather poor, as it does
not even cover the most vital references to philosophical sources on boredom.
The discussion on Heidegger is very short and many papers on boredom in his
oeuvre are not referenced. Moreover, Schopenhauer, Leopardi, Cioran, and Sartre are not mentioned; the only exception is
a brief discussion of Camus’ interpretation of Sisyphus’ myth. I would expect
better grounding in the boredom literature from a book about boredom, so as to avoid reinventing the wheel. The concept of
existential boredom should be more thoroughly introduced and analyzed to back the thesis about its universality.
Moreover, Gary proposes The Bell Jar by Sylvia Plath as his main
literary example of existential boredom. I am not at all sure that this is an
actual case of existential boredom, but, rather, depression—taking
into account the main character’s somatic symptoms. The concrete
differences between existential boredom and depression are challenging to
clearly explain but the two have been shown to be distinct (Bargdill,
2016; Goldberg et al., 2011). The discussion about existential boredom
should address such distinctions and nuances to be complete.
2. My second critical
point concerns the proposed remedy to boredom. The presented theory of leisure
resembles the concepts of flow (Csikszentmihalyi, 1991), momentum (Adler, 1981), or
mindfulness. These concepts should be critically discussed and compared to the
presented concept of leisure. My second point here is that the proposed
antidote to allegedly universal boredom seems to me to not be easily
implemented universally. In other words, the leisure presented by Gary appears
to be a rather difficult endeavour involving vigilance, discipline, and long
training. I doubt this solution is for everyone—this is rather an elitist and
philosophical proposition.
3. The last significant
doubt is the usage of primarily Christian sources on morality, as if Christian
sources were the ultimate source for discussions of morality. Although Gary
starts with Aristotle, he more often consults Thomas Aquinas, who baptized this
Greek philosopher. There are many references to St. Augustine and Christian
(mostly Catholic) theologians, not to mention Kierkegaard, a deeply Christian
philosopher. I am not convinced that academic books in the domain of moral
philosophy about boredom should be overwhelmingly based on Christian sources.
And if the author wants to adopt a Christian perspective, he should have
referenced the tradition of acedia. However, the concept of acedia is mentioned
only a few times in a rather cursory fashion. Gary claims that “modern boredom
arguably parallels acedia” (p. 7), is a precursor of boredom, and that the
perspective of Evagrius on boredom (actually on acedia) should be restored. Yet, the rich
historical sources on acedia and modern discussion on it are never employed in
the book, which I consider to be a significant omission in work on why boredom
as a moral problem matters.
Finally,
I would not be a proper bore if I did not mention some minor factual errors. In
the book, Peter Toohey is called a “philosopher” (p. 11)—he is actually a classical philologist. Later, Goetz et al.’s (2014) apathetic boredom is claimed to be “interchangeable with existential
boredom” (p. 28). This is definitely not the case, as
the authors did not employ the concept of existential boredom or even use the
word ‘existential’ in their paper. Finally, Gary uses the famous quote from
Tolstoy about “a desire for desire” (p. 32), claiming that Alexei Vronsky was a
protagonist of War and Peace while he was a character in Anna
Karenina.
Critical comments aside, Why Boredom Matters is an
interesting, well-written, and concise (about 130-page long) book for all those
who wonder whether there is an alternative to the capitalist, extremely bored,
busy self. Outside of, or rather aside from, boredom studies, Gary creates a
disciplined reflection over the problem of boredom proposing a challenging but
nevertheless so desperately-needed antidote to it. For
that, despite its limitations and shortcomings, it is worth noticing and
engaging in critical discussion.
References
Adler,
P. (1981). Momentum: A Theory of Social Action. Sage.
Bargdill, R. (2016). Habitual Boredom and Depression: Some Qualitative
Differences. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 59(2). https://doi.org/10.1177/0022167816637948
Brewer,
T. (2009). The Retrieval of Ethics. Oxford University Press.
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1991). Flow: The Psychology of Optimal
Experience. Harper Perennial.
Goetz,
T., Frenzel,
A., Hall, N., Nett, U., Pekrun, R., and Lipnevich, A. (2014). Types of Boredom: An Experience Sampling
Approach. Motivation and Emotion, 38, 401–419. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-013-9385-y
Goldberg,
Y., Eastwood, J., Laguardia, J., and Danckert, J. (2011). Boredom: An Emotional
Experience Distinct from Apathy, Anhedonia, or Depression. Journal of Social
and Clinical Psychology, 30(6), 647–666. https://doi.org/10.1521/jscp.2011.30.6.647
Leopardi,
G. (2015). Zibaldone. Palgrave Macmillan.
Svendsen,
L. (2016). Boredom and the Meaning of Life. In M. E. Gardiner and J. J. Haladyn (Eds.), Boredom Studies Reader: Frameworks and Perspectives (pp.
205–215). Routledge.
Toohey,
P. (2011). Boredom: A Lively History. Yale University Press.