Journal of Boredom
Studies (ISSN 2990-2525)
Issue 2, 2024, pp. 1–25
https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.10727142
https://www.boredomsociety.com/jbs
The Essence of Boredom: The Definition of Situational Boredom[1]
Mariusz Finkielsztein
Collegium Civitas,
Poland
mariusz.finkielsztein@gmail.com
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1620-9402
How to cite this paper: Finkielsztein,
M. (2024). The Essence of Boredom: The Definition of Situational Boredom. Journal
of Boredom Studies, 2.
https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.10727142
Abstract: Boredom frequently functions as a self-explanatory phenomenon
that is taken for granted, yet it is far from being one-dimensional and
obvious. The paper constitutes a critical analysis of qualities of boredom
employed in various definitions of boredom in order to
identify those essential for the phenomenon. The main goal of the paper is to
provide a summative reflection on definitions of boredom and to propose an
integrative definition of situational boredom, taking aside the problem of
separate and distinctive types of it, on the assumption that they are all only
dimensions of the core experience. The paper is based on an analysis of
literature on boredom from several fields, including psychology, philosophy,
anthropology, educational and work studies, and sociology (n=572). The paper
specifies non-essential (idleness, rest, laziness, apathy, monotony, lack of
interest, and slow passage of time) and essential (being an emotion/feeling,
perceived as aversive, combining listlessness and restlessness, disengagement,
meaninglessness, and liminality) elements in defining boredom and construct the
definition of situational boredom as ‘a transient, negatively perceived,
transitional emotion or feeling of listless and restless inattention to and
engagement withdrawal from interacting with one’s social and/or physical
environment caused distinctively by an atrophy of personally-valued meaning,
the frustrated need for meaning.’
Keywords: boredom,
situational boredom, definition of boredom, interactionism, interdisciplinary.
1. Introduction
The aim of this paper is
to provide a summative reflection on definitions of boredom in
an attempt to propose a ‘gist’ conceptualisation of the phenomenon (in
the form of novel, inclusive definition of boredom) that I hope proves useful
to researchers irrespective of discipline. Thereby, it constitutes an attempt
to offer a new approach towards the conceptualization of situational boredom,
which thus far has received relatively scant attention from boredom researchers
(the chapter by Wolff et al. [2022] and Ros Velasco’s book [2022] are rare exceptions). The paper is based on
an analysis of interdisciplinary literature, encompassing work in psychology,
philosophy, anthropology, educational and work studies, and sociology (n=572).
Useful for theoretical reflection presented in the paper is also the fact that
I have researched boredom using qualitative methods since 2011. The first part
of the title of this paper references an influential article written by William
Mikulas and Stephen Vodanovich (1993), as my work is meant to both challenge and develop their reflections
in a broader and more interdisciplinary direction, including both psychological
and sociological approaches to boredom. The paper is organized as follows.
First, I explain the nature of situational boredom. Next, I argue that boredom
has been poorly conceptualized. Then, I list definitional elements that have
been deemed important in the literature on boredom that, in my view, are
insufficient, irrelevant, or just not essential for defining the phenomenon,
and I provide a justification of my stance. Subsequently, I discuss
definitional components that I consider essential and similarly justify my
choice. Finally, I propose an original definition of situational boredom and a
short analysis of its applicability. The main goal of the paper is to propose
an integrative definition of situational boredom, taking aside the problem of
separate and distinctive types of it (see Elpidorou, 2021; Goetz et al., 2014), on the assumption that they are
all only dimensions of the core experience.
There
seems to be a general consensus among boredom
researchers that two major kinds of boredom can be differentiated. For the sake
of clarity, I will loosely characterize them as ‘simple boredom’ and ‘complex
boredom.’ The former is usually seen as more mundane and the latter as more
severe. There are various criteria according to which authors differentiate
between them, but the main line of division is usually whether boredom is
induced by/anchored in/associated with an external situation/environment or the
individual. The following terms have been used to describe these two types of
boredom: reactive and endogenous boredom (Neu, 1998);
situation-dependent and situation-independent boredom (Todman,
2003); responsive and chronic boredom (Bernstein, 1975), episodic and chronic boredom (Mael and Jex, 2015), state and trait boredom (Mikulas and Vodanovich, 1993), and
situational/situative and existential boredom
(Svendsen, 2005; Toohey, 2011).
The
first type of boredom has been characterised as (1)
transient/transitory/short-lived, (2) normal/justifiable/‘innocent’/conscious,
(3) directly observable, (4) easily induced and alleviated (5)
affective/emotional state being a reaction/response to (6) a concrete/real
situation/task at hand/external circumstances/objects. This type of boredom is
rather superficial and almost entirely dependent on external factors, and it disappears when its causes are removed (Healy, 1984; Irvine, 2001; Kuhn, 1976; Toohey,
2011).
The
second type of boredom can be characterised as (1) long-lasting/chronic, (2)
pathological/non-normal, (3) abstract/not directly observable, (4) highly
enduring/persistent, (5) an existential state/mood, (6) endogenous/internal
to/deeply-rooted in the individual’s self (Elpidorou,
2017b; Fahlman et al., 2013). This type of boredom is understood in at least three ways (depending
on discipline and approach) as: (1) a personal trait (boredom proneness:
differential psychology), (2) an attitude towards or perception of one’s
existence (existential, profound boredom: philosophical existentialism and
pessimism), or (3) a pathological response to or an outcome of unconscious
processes (psychodynamic approach). I present this description for
informational purposes and will not discuss this type of boredom any further,
as the paper is solely devoted to the analysis of situational boredom.
2. Poor Conceptualization of Boredom
Boredom seems to be
commonly thought to be self-explanatory, needing no verbal definition, even
among many researchers who study it. When challenged to actually
specify/express the meaning of boredom, individuals struggle. Boredom is like “[m]ost things immersed in daily life [that] one understands fairly
enough until asked to define them” (Bauman, 2000, p. 110).
However, in this respect, boredom is much like most emotions, which are, for
the main part, taken for granted. Everyone seems to know “what an emotion is
until asked to give a definition. Then, it seems, no one knows” (Fehr and
Russell, 1984, p. 464). In much of the existing literature
on boredom, authors not always employ
comprehensive definitions of the phenomenon in question. Out of 572 texts with
the word ‘boredom’ in the title to which I have had access (journal articles,
books, books chapters, MA/PhD theses written in English [507] and Polish [65]),[2]
analysed in the present study, only 36 (6.29%) provide a more or less original
definition of boredom, 161 (28.15%) cite definitions presented by other authors
(more than 50% cite one of three definitions coined respectively by Fisher [1993], Mikulas and
Vodanovich [1993], or Eastwood et al. [2012]), 117 (20.45%) use some definitional
expressions, frequently delivered in metaphorical/poetic language, which I call
quasi-definitions (cf. “impressionistic definitions,” Meyer Spacks, 1995, p. 14), and 258
(45.11%) employ no definition at all.
The above-mentioned
analysis was based on the following principle. I consider a ‘definition’ to be
an intentional/connotative definition aimed at capturing the essence of a
defined object which traditionally consists of two elements: genus (a large category) and differentia (distinguishing
characteristics). In my analysis, if a definition under consideration had both
elements and was not cited with a reference, I coded it as ‘an original
definition’; if a definition was not formally correct or was not meant to be an
actual definition at all (e.g., was not introduced by ‘boredom is...’), but
still aimed at describing some essential qualities of the phenomenon, I coded
it as ‘a quasi-definition.’ Nevertheless, the most disturbing and shocking
fact, in my view, is that almost half of all analysed texts did not employ any
definitions at all. The term ‘boredom’ was employed in its common, colloquial,
taken-for-granted sense (see Darden and Marks, 1999), on the premise that everybody knows what
boredom is. In my opinion, such a presumption constitutes a serious
methodological problem, because—as I discovered upon reviewing the
literature—the conceptualisation of boredom is far from unambiguous and univocal.
One may even say that various authors speak “about separate constructs, though
each one is referred to as boredom” (Baratta, 2014, p. 2) and that they
“speak not of boredom, but of boredoms” (Phillips, 1993, p. 82), as the term might be just a “grab bag of a term” (Beres, 2017), a kind of umbrella term for many various related but separate
phenomena.
Having
no definition is a problem, but so is having an empty/vague definition. The
first issue in this regard is the self-explanatory character of some
definitions, i.e. circular definitions. Merriam-Webster’s Student Dictionary
(2004), for instance,
explains ‘boredom’ as “the condition of being bored,” “to bore” as “to weary by
monotony, dullness,” and ‘dull’ simply as “boring.” Given that tedium and
dullness are considered synonyms of boredom, defining one by referring to
another provides no extra information to those who do not already know the
meaning of these words. Such circular definitions are also evident in some
papers on the subject, where boredom is described, for instance, as being “a
reactive state to wearingly dull or tedious stimuli” (Musharbash,
2007, p. 307) or “the
reflection of objective dullness” (Adorno, 2001, p. 192).
The second issue is oversimplifying, i.e., reducing
boredom to a traditionally identified limited set of characteristics/keywords.
This pertains to many definitions coined in dictionaries. The
most popular English dictionary conceptualises boredom as “the state of being weary
and restless through lack of interest” (Merriam-Webster, n.d.). The same practice can be observed in dictionaries of other languages.
For example, in Polish, boredom is commonly defined as “an unpleasant state or
feeling caused usually by idleness,
lack of interesting occupation, lack of excitement, monotony of life” (Szymczak, 1995) or in
German as a “depressing feeling of having no occupation” (Digitales Wörterbuch der deutschen Sprache, n.d.). All these definitions provide no information about the essence of the
experience, and little information about its causes. Defining boredom by its
causes instead of specifying its differentiating characteristics may constitute
a more general problem of defining affective states (Daschmann
et al., 2011; Eastwood et al., 2012).
One more definitional problem is the formal negativity of
some definitions, i.e., describing boredom by enumerating what boredom is not.
The definition of ennui in The Great French Encyclopaedia can serve
as an extreme example of the case:
[Boredom is] a kind of displeasure
which cannot be defined; it is neither sorrow nor sadness; it is a privation of
all pleasure, caused by I do not know what in our organs or in external
objects, which, instead of occupying our soul, produces a malaise or disgust,
which we cannot be accustomed to (Jaucourt, 1772).
This appears to be a
method to avoid defining the phenomenon rather than explaining its essence in a
comprehensive way. Yet, paradoxically, perhaps the tendency to define boredom
by negation lies in the very essence of boredom, insofar as it is deemed to be
an ambivalent, obscure and shapeless experience: “lack, void or absence, which
can only be determined by a difference” (Markowski, 1999, p. 290).
Another definitional issue is the tendency to, instead of
risking a formal definition, provide a more or less general,
poetic, metaphorical or just partial expression. One may argue that perhaps
such explanations of boredom could be even more revealing and touch upon the
kernel of the phenomenon, but I argue that they are, for the most part,
one-dimensional and limited in their explanatory capacities. The bulk of such
expressions provide an important insight into the essence of boredom but cannot
serve as scientific conceptualisations of the phenomenon. By way of example,
boredom is described as “the growing awareness of nothingness” (Mijuskovic, 1979, p. 20, quoted in in Kirova, 2004, p. 244), “extreme aesthesia” (Aho, 2007, title), “the dream bird that hatches the egg of experience” (Benjamin,
2007, p. 91), “a psychic anorexia” (Healy, 1984, p. 60), “the lassitude of the soul” (Sandywell,
2011, p. 177), “experience without qualities”
(Goodstein, 2005, title), “the longing for a content”
(Marx, 1992, p. 398), or “a form of devastating agony”
(Seo, 2003, p. 3). Some of the above wordings are
strictly emphatic and poetic, with no exclusive connection to boredom (e.g.
‘lassitude of the soul’ may be a proper characterization of depression as well,
and ‘devastating agony’ of many other states); others are more concrete and,
arguably, more closely connected with boredom (‘extreme anaesthesia’ or
‘psychic anorexia’). Nevertheless, none of these can serve as a proper
scientific definition of the phenomenon.
3. Non-Essential Elements in Defining
Boredom
In this section, I take
a closer look at several qualities frequently mentioned in definitions of
boredom which I find insufficient, irrelevant, or just not essential for the
phenomenon in question. As non-essential I classify those elements that, basing
on existing knowledge, seem to be rather causes or consequences of boredom and
not integral qualities of the mere experience of the emotion in question. As
essential I deem those elements that seem inherent and universal to all
instances of actual experience of boredom. The non-essential elements in
defining boredom I analyse in this section are: (1) idleness/low
level of arousal; (2) rest; (3) laziness; (4) apathy; (5) repetition/monotony;
(6) lack of interest; (7) slow passage of time.
3.1. Idleness/Low Level of Arousal
First
of all, boredom
is frequently associated with idleness, and even defined as its close synonym.
Yet, I argue that it is not at all equal with boredom as it is not the same as
doing nothing (see the 6th myth about boredom in Ros Velasco, 2023). In my view, inactivity is only one of many circumstances under which
boredom arises. Clearly enough, if it were an essential feature of boredom,
work would be the most effective remedy for it. Admittedly, such a vision of
boredom proliferated in the Enlightenment (Helvétius,
1810; Krasicki, 1994; Voltaire, 2006). However, as indicated by the
findings of countless studies dealing with work and employment, many people
experience boredom while performing their jobs (among other, Loukidou et al., 2009; Rothlin and Werder, 2008; Van Hooff and Van Hooft, 2014). In
brief, work cures merely idleness but not boredom (Kierkegaard, 1843), as it “is not the disease of
being bored because there’s nothing to do, but the more serious disease of
feeling that there’s nothing worth doing” (Pessoa, 2002, sec.
445). Using more ‘scientific’ language (as idleness
is quite a common expression), boredom is also defined as “an affective state
that can be connected to low levels of arousal” (Giakoumis et al., 2011, p. 121), “the tension created by the lack of neural nourishment”
(Saunders, 1996, p. 465), “understimulation
stress” (de la Peña, 2006), or “a feeling of mental
weariness, listless discontent, produced by want of an occupation” (Gabriel, 1988, p. 157). Lack of stimulation, and a resulting low level of cortical
arousal, in my opinion is not essential for boredom, as there are other
affective states also characterised by a low level of arousal (e.g. sadness,
dejection, laziness).
3.2. Rest
In many press articles,
boredom seems to be a virtual synonym for rest or relaxation, for which most
people do not have enough time in current achievement society. Such a view is
shared by some scholars as well; boredom is described, for instance, as “a
yawning empty chasm between two meaningful moments” (Gabelman,
2010, p. 147). Along the same lines, Walter
Benjamin (2007) famously claimed that “if sleep is
the apogee of physical relaxation, boredom is the apogee of mental relaxation”
(p. 91). Yet, what proves crucial
in defining boredom is the subject’s negative perception of the feeling (Macklem, 2015). In cases where one perceives
one’s idleness or low intensity activity as beneficial and purposeful (e.g.
resting, meditating), boredom is not in the picture at all. The state of low
arousal and satisfaction constitutes a state of relaxation and peacefulness (Mikulas and Vodanovich, 1993).
Boredom does take place when one is inactive and, at the same time, does not
want to stay inactive any longer. In this context, it is
connected with dissatisfaction and functions as a universal signal that
something needs to be changed in the current situation (Elpidorou,
2017a).
3.3. Laziness
Also frequently
associated with boredom, laziness constitutes a state of generic slowness,
inactivity and disinclination towards activity. To some authors, it is a
synonym of boredom (e.g. Fromm, 2002; Gurycka,
1977) or a cause of it (Kabzińska,
2015; Krasicki, 1994). This can be aptly illustrated by quoting Erich Fromm: “Laziness, far
from being normal, is a symptom of mental pathology. In fact, one of the worst
forms of mental suffering is boredom, not knowing what to do with oneself and
one’s life” (2002, p. 282). However, since boredom
leaves the individual craving stimulation (see the section on restlessness
below), with a host of mental and behavioural consequences, which include, in
some cases, hyperactivity/restlessness/fidgetiness (e.g. Burn, 2017; Kenny, 2009; Phillips, 1993), laziness cannot be a sine qua non of the phenomenon. To my mind, it
is, rather one of the possible outcomes of boredom (Rothlin
and Werder, 2008) or of its anticipation—one usually
gets lazy when they are not willing to do something that they expect to be
boring, unpleasant, difficult and/or wearisome (see more in Finkielsztein,
2018).
3.4. Apathy
To some authors, boredom
has direct connotations of apathy, emotional detachment, “affective deficiency,”
and “affective lack” (Ngai, 2005, pp. 268, 269). In this respect, it
is defined as a state of “not having any feelings, being blocked emotionally,
being frozen, feeling the self to be unreal, in a word, apathy” (Bibring, 1953, p. 28, quoted in Kenny, 2009, p. 139). Some define boredom as a state of “general listlessness”
(Csikszentmihalyi, 2000, p. 442) and “emotional flatness
and resigned indifference” (Gardiner, 2014, p. 30).
Nevertheless, it is evidently well-distinguishable from apathy, as apathy
constitutes a total lack of emotions, lack of motivation and “a failure to seek
alternatives” (Bench and Lench, 2013, p. 463), whereas boredom spurs one’s motivation to change the current
activity and to pursue an alternative set of actions. As Ralph Greenson (1953) noted, in patients suffering from apathy, in contrast to those
afflicted with boredom, “there is no more longing and a far greater inhibition
of the ego’s thinking and perceptive functions” (p. 12). As Wolff et al. (2022) state, both boredom and apathy are associated with a decrease in
interest, but “in boredom this decrease in interest is directed at the current
situation (i.e., is specific to the current experience, and increases with
respect to other stimuli resulting in a shift of attention),” while in apathy
we observe a decrease in interest “with respect to most stimuli” (p. 17). They also
note the differences in motivation: apathy is connected to a motivation
decrease to all stimuli, while boredom increases motivation for seeking
alternative stimuli. Apathy
is, thus, a more radical state, whose scope, to some extent, may overlap that
of boredom (in its listless part) but lacks many other qualities of it (see the
detailed discussion in the second part of this paper). It may also be one of
possible outcomes of boredom.
3.5. Repetition/Monotony
Many researchers and
theorists have claimed that one of the essential qualities of boredom is
repetition and monotony (Brodsky, 1995; Davies, 1926; Drory, 1982; Hill, 1975;
O’Hanlon, 1981). In industrial studies, for
instance, boredom for many decades functioned as a synonym of monotony (Davies,
1926). In such conceptualisations, the causes of
the phenomenon are attributed to occupational deprivation (Wilcock, 2006), “exposure to monotonous stimulation” (O’Hanlon, 1981, p. 54), “an environment which is unchanging or which changes in a
repetitive and a highly predictable fashion” (Davies et al., 1983, p. 1). However, the findings of a large number of
studies indicate that these features do not necessarily induce boredom. The
following three examples clarify the point: (1) students can get bored in
lectures which are far from being monotonous (Finkielsztein,
2013), (2) some industrial workers even
express a preference for routine tasks, arguing that those provide them with an
opportunity to focus their thoughts elsewhere, typically on more pleasurable
activities (Watt, 2002), (3) artists who, like musicians
or dancers, need to regularly or repeatedly practise some basic exercises do
not get bored with the routine (except among some child musicians [Wagner, 2015]). When, in the
eyes of the person who has settled down into a routine, it is meaningful and
purposeful, the routine does not cause boredom and may even provide them with a
sense of security and belongingness (Barbalet, 1999; Klapp, 1986; Winter,
2002). Therefore, monotony is only one of the
possible causes of boredom (Daschmann et al., 2011; Harris, 2000; Hill and Perkins, 1985; Vogel-Walcutt
et al., 2012) and is not at all essential to the
feeling.
3.6. Lack of Interest
Another common view is
that boredom is principally characterised by lack of interest, and that,
perforce, interest or curiosity is its ultimate antithesis (Bruss, 2012; Chapman, 2013; Meyer Spacks, 1995). Yet, boredom has a multidimensional character and significantly
differs from a simple lack of interest. Lack of interest is affectively
neutral, implying neither the wish to engage in the situation at hand nor the
wish to escape from it (Preckel et al., 2010, p. 454), whereas boredom is clearly affectively negative. One can be
not interested in classical ballet yet not bored by it, because they never go
to a ballet performance (Svendsen, 2016). I can feel disinterest in many topics, and it does not provoke any
affective reaction in me. I simply do not care about them. Boredom constitutes
rather “a state of strong counterinterest” (Healy, 1984, p. 58) and what definitions usually mean by lack of interest is the situations in
which we are exposed on something that we actively do not care⸻so
when, for instance, someone forces us to do something that we are not
interested in doing. But then, lack of interest starts to be a cause of boredom
and not the essential quality of the emotion itself. Lack of interest, therefore, is not essential
to boredom, either.
3.7. Slow Passage of
Time
While many theorists
have eloquently argued for a close connection between boredom and the
experience of time dragging (e.g. Heidegger, 1995;
Safranski, 2015; Zakay, 2014), I treat it rather as a consequence of boredom, a significant
concomitant thereof. This conclusion is strongly favoured by the very premises
of cognitive psychological theories of time perception. According to the scalar
expectancy theory (Gibbon, 1977), perception of time is a
consequence of attentional processes. Each organism has an internal clock, a
kind of pacemaker that emits temporal pulses. Those signals are accumulated
throughout a given time interval (event/activity)—the more pulses registered,
the stronger the sensation that the time interval lasts longer, in other words,
that time passes more slowly. When we are engaged in something, our attention
is focused on it and we do not spot all the temporal pulses; thus, time seems
to move faster. In boredom, we are basically unengaged, and we perceive more
temporal pulses because we more consciously experience the passage of time.
Consequently, the time seems to drag on. In other words, when someone is not
engaged in an activity, they allocate more attentional resources to the passage
of time, which creates the impression that time is moving slowly. That this is
the case has been corroborated by, among others, Laird (2007), London
and Monello (1974) and
Bench and Lench (2013).
4. Essential Elements in Defining Boredom
This section is devoted
to identifying and explaining all those qualities of boredom that, according to
my perspective, constitute the essence of boredom, i.e. are an inherent quality
of experiencing the emotion in question. As such elements I classify: (1) being
an emotion or feeling; (2) negativity or aversive nature of such a state; (3)
the combination of listlessness and restlessness; (4) disengagement/attention
withdrawal; (5) sense of meaninglessness; and (6) liminality/transitionality.
4.1. Emotion/Feeling
Many authors define
boredom by using the amorphous word ‘state’ or the general term ‘affect,’ which
includes all affective states (emotion, feeling and mood; Zhu and Zhou, 2012), while others characterise boredom as simply a drive (for novelty,
stimuli, etc.). All the same, the most frequently used genera are ‘emotion’ and
‘feeling,’ terms whose differences in meaning seem rarely to be analysed. Upon
confronting boredom with psychological definitions of emotions, one comes to the conclusion that it perfectly fits into those
conceptualisations and can be successfully defined as an emotion. Accordingly,
boredom is a short-lived, subjective, psycho-physiological affective state that
can be described as having five components (see Macklem,
2015): (1) affective (an unpleasant, negative
feeling), (2) physiological (a non-optimal level of arousal), (3) cognitive (a
low level of attention, the perception of time dragging on), (4) motivational
(disinclination towards the activity/situation at hand), and (5) expressive (a
slumped posture, drowsiness).
However,
a definitional problem begins with the term ‘feeling,’ which is frequently used
interchangeably with “emotion” (Mulligan and Scherer, 2012, p. 353)
and is used as an integral part of its definition (many definitions of emotion
start with the phrase ‘emotion is a feeling…’). Here, I follow the strain of
the theoretical reflection which interprets ‘feeling’ as a conscious experience
of emotion, one of its symptoms (Damasio, 1999; Frijda, 1986; Prinz, 2005). In
this conceptualisation, emotions are merely “unconscious perceptions of
patterned changes in the body” (Prinz, 2005, p. 17),
“a physical response to change that is hard-wired and universal” (Meyer, n.d.). Psychologists and philosophers argue that emotions (e.g., boredom)
can manifest themselves in an individual’s behaviour and physiology without
being revealed in a subjective experience (Prinz, 2005; Sartre,
1962). Emotions are non-reflexive phenomena, which
means that people can experience them without being aware of the fact (see Raposa, 1999; Svendsen, 2005). By the same token, one “can live in boredom
without feeling it” (Schielke, 2008, p. 257). Feelings, on the other hand, are “mental associations and
reactions to an emotion that are personal, acquired through experience” (Meyer,
n.d.). Thus, emotions are generally conceived of as
being unconscious, whereas feelings are considered to be
conscious. To reiterate, a feeling constitutes the conscious mode of an
emotion, its extension towards the realm of awareness. In the present
conceptualisation, therefore, boredom is treated as either an emotion if
unconscious or a feeling if conscious.
As
mentioned above, boredom, as an emotion, is a relatively transient and
situation-dependent experience in most cases. Often it is more a ‘conveyor
belt’ to other emotions/states of mind than a clearly recognisable/distinctive,
long-term experience in its own right. Experiencing
boredom signals that a particular mental/physical activity does not meet one’s
expectations, does not satisfy one’s need for meaningfulness, and that another,
more valuable engagement should be sought (see Barbalet,
1999; Brisset and Snow, 1993; Meyer Spacks, 1995). Because of this, boredom can
disappear at the very moment it emerges, as almost immediately one begins to
search for another activity. Frequently, boredom is quickly replaced by other
emotions such as frustration, anxiety, anger, etc. The process is, by nature,
rather swift and quasi-mechanical, for emotions flow smoothly into one another
(see Strelau and Doliński, 2011).
4.2. Negativity/Aversion
Boredom is also commonly
perceived as an aversive state. This conclusion was drawn by Vogel-Walcutt et al. (2012) in their review of the literature,
and by Baratta (2014), with
half of the definitions under her analysis including the component of
negativity/aversion. My textual analysis of definitions of boredom in the
literature thoroughly corroborates the findings of those studies. Boredom is
frequently associated with the feeling of dissatisfaction and is reported to be
positively correlated with the occurrences of other negative affective states
and emotions such as loneliness, anger, sadness, worry (Chin et al., 2017) and frustration (Hill and Perkins, 1985). This
is not to say that boredom is negative in the sense of being maladaptive, as it
may have many positive outcomes and serve various functions (Elpidorou, 2016, 2017a), but rather that its perception is
negative/aversive. I am of the opinion that boredom as
such is neither positive nor negative, but it can only have positive or
negative consequences. Thus, what is essential in defining boredom is the
negative perception of boredom rather than the negativity of the phenomenon
itself.
4.3.
Listlessness/Restlessness
I argue that boredom is
a distinctive state characterised simultaneously by listlessness and
restlessness which, however, are motivationally opposing and each of which is
indispensable and essential to the experience. Listlessness alone would
constitute the state of apathy, and restlessness merely a kind of nervousness.
On the one hand, there are innumerable testimonies characterising boredom as a
sort of freezing, lack of energy, weariness, lethargy, stagnation, paralysis,
anaesthesia, indifference, emotional flatness or lack of care (Bargdill, 2000; Beckelman,
1995; Frederiksen, 2017;
Gabriel, 1988; Gardiner, 2014; Kenny, 2009; Wechter-Ashkin,
2010; Thiele, 1997). This
characterisation was corroborated in my research among university students (Finkielsztein, 2013), who
described boredom as, among other things, ‘freezing/spacing out’,
‘hibernation,’ ‘sleep mode’ or ‘quieting the mind.’ On the other hand, boredom
is connected with a high motivation for stimulation (Burn, 2017), a constant search for novelty (Mosurinjohn,
2016), and agitation (Fenichel,
1951; Wechter-Ashkin, 2010). Boredom is believed to create ‘undirected motion,’ i.e. “motor or
mental changes away from the state that caused boredom” (Wolff et al., 2022, p. 10). In this context, boredom implies “a longing to engage in an unspecified satisfying activity” (Baratta, 2014, p. 21), ‘a call to action’ (Danckert and Elpidorou, 2023) and is defined as the state “of diffuse
restlessness which contains that most absurd and paradoxical wish, the wish for
a desire” (Phillips, 1993, p. 68). Putting it in terms of
arousal, there is some evidence that boredom is both a high and a low arousal
state, as it has been found to be positively correlated with both restlessness
and sleepiness (Danckert et al., 2018).
This duality is reflected in the distinction between
apathetic and agitated boredom (Fenichel, 1951), or between listless and restless boredom (Sundberg and Bisno, 1983), which specifies two major possible manifestations of boredom. One can
become either lethargic or overactive. In other words, one can react to the
core experience of boredom by further deactivation or by attempting to
re-engage. From this perspective, listlessness and restlessness are basically
outcomes of the feeling rather than ingredients of its essence. However, I
argue that both are always present in boredom, with one of them prevailing over
the other. Accordingly, to be bored is to experience listlessness and
restlessness at the same time, with the former being directed towards the
situation at hand and the latter being directed towards a prospective activity,
specifically, escaping from the anesthetising experience (in that sense,
boredom is functional; see among others Elpidorou, 2017a). As Wendell O’Brien (2014) puts
it, when speaking of his boredom: “I am weary with one thing and restless for
another” (p. 239).
In this context, I endorse a position close to those of Baratta (2014), who described boredom as
simultaneously lethargic/deactivated and restless, and Elpidorou (2016), who defined boredom as a state of
dissatisfaction, restlessness, and weariness. This coexistence of such opposite
states is also corroborated by some empirical data derived from the field of
existential psychology. A patient analysed by John Maltsberger
(2000, p. 84) described his boredom in a way that
clarifies my point: “I feel discontented, restless, and anxious, yet at the
same time lethargic, indifferent, unmotivated, unmoved, an automaton” (cf.
Martin et al., 2006).
4.4.
Disengagement/Attention Withdrawal
In microsociology,
boredom is conceptualised, in the first place, as a social emotion that emerges
when an interaction between social actors lacks qualities necessary to arouse
engagement, flow and/or effective communication. The social world is a place of
constant interactions and communication with others (Berger and Luckmann, 1991). Boredom is a strictly relational
and relative concept, being a matter of interpretation and of relationships
established between people, or between people and objects (Mansikka,
2009; Raposa, 1999). Boredom is primarily the experience of disengagement from an
interaction. This is the situation where “an individual experiences being out
of synch with the ongoing rhythms of social life,” “being disengaged from the
ebb and flow of human interaction” (Brisset and Snow,
1993, pp. 239, 241) and “not being involved in or
engaged by events or activities” (Barbalet, 1999, p. 634). Boredom “frequently ends an interaction” (Darden and Marks, 1999, p. 27), and throws the individual “in a kind of social limbo” (Kenny, 2009, p. 9).
In my conceptualisation, I apply the basic principles of
such a relational/interactional perspective on boredom. In this framework, I
indicate that essential for boredom is some form of lack of engagement (Brisset and Snow, 1993; Darden
and Marks, 1999; Eastwood et al., 2012; Goffman, 1982), of disconnection and withdrawal
of attention (Healy, 1984; Klapp, 1986), which is, to my mind, the psychological term describing substantially
the same experience (disengagement is always the case of inattention).
Contrarily to the Boredom Feedback Model (BFM; Tam et al., 2021), which
associates the feeling of boredom to “the discrepancy between one’s actual
level (i.e., objectively measurable) of attentional engagement and subjectively
desired level of attentional engagement” (p. 4), my proposition implies
‘attentional disengagement’ (cf. Danckert and Elpidorou, 2023) as essential for the emotion in
question. Boredom, in the presented conceptualisation, constitutes withdrawal
from interaction with the social and/or physical environment (e.g. when one is
alone). It is a relational state characterised by lack of involvement in any
kind of social or non-social activity, neglect of or withdrawal from active and
genuine participation in interaction with other people or objects. Boredom is a
form of disconnection, zoning out, switching off, or inattentiveness.
4.5. Meaninglessness
The fundamental premise
of my conceptualisation is that the process of sense-making is essential for
human beings, that humans “are addicted to meaning” (Svendsen, 2005, p. 30; cf. Frankl, 2000). In
normal, everyday conditions, people usually manage to successfully satisfy
their urge for meaning, but when they fail to do so, boredom emerges as a
signal of “the inability to realize this desire” (Misztal,
2016, p. 102). Thus, to my way of thinking, boredom
constitutes a feeling of absence of meaning (Baratta,
2014; Barbalet, 1999), “a meaning withdrawal” (Svendsen, 2005, p. 30).
Moreover, I argue that if there is one unique feature of boredom which could be
broadly perceived as central to the experience, it certainly is a sense of
meaninglessness. Many boredom researchers (Chan et al., 2018; Elpidorou, 2017a; Martin
et al., 2006; Van Tilburg and Igou, 2012) appear to have developed views that converge, at least in part, with
mine. Meaning deficit (Svendsen, 2005), the
perception of an activity as meaningless (Barbalet, 1999; Van Tilburg and Igou, 2012), proves quintessential to boredom.
First, out of a number of important elements of the
experience, it is the one that knits all of them together and, secondly, is not
shared with any other affective state (depression is a mood). There are other
unpleasant affective states (e.g. anxiety, disgust, worry, irritation), some of
which can be associated with disengagement, listlessness (e.g. sadness) or
restlessness (e.g. impatience, frustration). Some researchers, especially
psychologists, argue that the lack of meaning is a cause of boredom (de Chenne, 1998; Fahlman et al., 2009; Hill and Perkins, 1985; MacDonald and Holland, 2002), a position with which I generally agree. However, to be more
specific, I claim that an atrophy of meaning is a distinctive and essential
feature/cause of boredom. What I mean by this is the subject’s
personally-perceived lack of meaning in a concrete situation—not general
meaninglessness of some kind of activity. I claim, contrarily to the MAC model
by Westgate and Wilson (2018), that there is no possibility for
one to be bored and simultaneously to perceive the situation as personally
meaningful. In other words, the essential for boredom is both inattention and
sense of meaninglessness. If one feels bored, it means that one does not assess
the particular situation as personally valuable at the
moment and would prefer to do something else instead. If one truly finds
meaning in one’s occupation, one never gets bored by it. If one feels bored, it
means that, at least at that moment and in the specific circumstances, one does
not evaluate the task/activity/situation as meaningful for oneself. The task as
such may remain ‘objectively’ meaningful to somebody who performs it, but
carrying it out can be, at times, boring—under certain conditions, in
particular situations. To illustrate the point, teachers who like their job and
find it generally meaningful and rewarding may, in some situations, feel bored
with their teaching performance, when its actual meaning becomes questionable
to them due to adverse conditions (e.g., they feel exhausted, or the students
are not engaged in the learning process).
4.5.1. Meaning
Frustration
Associated with
disappointment, frustration is defined as “irritable distress after a wish
collided with an unyielding reality” (Jeronimus and Laceulle, 2017, p. 1), or ‘failure of
expectations’ (Conrad, 1997, p. 474). It can be either a cause
or a consequence of boredom (Baker et al., 2010; Wechter-Ashkin, 2010; Vogel-Walcutt
et al., 2012), but boredom can be as well “only another
name for a certain species of frustration” (Sontag, 1967, p.
303). I claim not that boredom is a frustration, as the correlation between the
two are not sufficiently high (Struk et al., 2021), but a kind of meaning frustration, i.e., an emotional reaction to the
unfulfilled need for meaning or to the unsuccessful construction of meaning. If
we assume, after Viktor Frankl (2000), that humans constantly ‘search
for meaning,’ which I find correct, as people never willingly perform
activities they perceive to be personally meaningless (i.e., without some
rationalisation or imagined functionality), boredom constitutes a reaction to a
situation in which this pursuit fails and the individual is left with the
frustrated need for meaning.
4.6. Liminality/Transitionality
The last essential
feature of boredom is its liminal/transitional character. It is described as a
kind of captivity, entrapment (Martin et al., 2006;
O’Neill, 2014; Wechter-Ashkin,
2010), stuckness
in-between, in some transitional state of suspended present, un-realisation. It
involves a situation in which the past is “no more”
and the future is “not yet” (Frederiksen, 2013, p. 6).
Boredom is a state of suspension between engagements—one involvement has ceased
but another has not yet begun. I conceive boredom as ‘a conveyor belt’ to other
emotions or activities. If the individual quickly manages to transition to a
new activity/mental engagement/emotion, the transitional state can take just a
moment, and, thus, go undetected—as it actually often
does. This interpretation seems to be reinforced by the fact that one is
frequently unaware of situational boredom. All the same, when the conveyor belt
goes on and on, with no conceivable destination, the sense of being stuck in
the transition can become a mood or a steady disposition (chronic/existential
boredom). In this sense, boredom is characteristic of any on-going transitions that
inhibit the process of becoming. It may emerge in situations of major activity
changes in life—when the old pattern has expired, and a new one has not yet
been established. It is, therefore, a matter of a sudden drop in the
individual’s activity level characterised by the feeling of indeterminacy. A
few typical situations to illustrate the point are: losing one’s job,
graduating from school/university, a transition between the army and college (Fisher,
1987) or parents’ experience of an ‘empty nest’
after the children have ‘suddenly’ left home (Rogge, 2011).
The
long-term liminality under discussion, a kind of suspension, is described by
Alfred de Musset (2006) in his autobiographical novel The Confession of a Child of the Century.
Written in the Romantic era, it depicts the painful experience of striving
desperately to burst through old and cramping patterns and yearning for
unachievable goals. The pain pervaded the whole generation of Romantics, who
spent their adolescence in the frivolous, adventurous times of the Napoleonic
era and reached adulthood after the Congress of Vienna, in a time of
stagnation: “That which was is no more; what will be, is not yet. Do not seek
elsewhere the cause of our malady” (de Musset, 2006). That
‘malady’ was vastly influenced by boredom, ‘the Great Ennui’ (Steiner, 1971).
Yet another illustration of the indeterminacy of
protracted transition is the case of young Native Americans on the Grass Creek
Reservation (Jervis et al., 2003). At present, their native
tradition (their cultural inheritance) is losing its significance and is in
danger of extinction. At the same time, new cultural patterns (the mainstream
culture) are, as of now, out of reach. Consequently, a void has opened up which breeds boredom and unease. The high
likelihood of the void becoming, after a prolonged period of time, their
deeply-internalized everydayness is evidenced, for example, by the homeless in
post-communist Romania, who live “at the margins in limbo, between a nostalgia
for a brutal past and a resignation toward a hopeless future” (O’Neill, 2014, p. 24).
Boredom, in this sense, may be metaphorically compared to
the situation of a rite of passage which has got stuck in the middle—one is
already deprived of the attributes of one’s former position but not yet
included within the realm of one’s new status—a bored individual is marginalised
and their status is ambivalent (Van Gennep, 1960). To sum up, a bored person is imprisoned in a kind of limbo, stuck
between activities, statuses, experiences, or engagements (see Finkielsztein, 2021) and, in
this sense, I define boredom as a liminal/transitional emotion that constitutes
a typically brief period of suspension, ‘betweenness.’
5.
Definition and Its Applicability
Taking into
consideration all of the above described essential
components of boredom, I define situational boredom as follows:
Boredom is a
transient, negatively perceived, transitional emotion or feeling of listless
and restless inattention to and engagement withdrawal from interacting with
one’s social and/or physical environment caused distinctively by an atrophy of personally-valued meaning, the frustrated need for meaning.
Therefore, I construe boredom essentially as a state of
inattention/disengagement prompted by a sense of meaninglessness, involving a
suspension between two activities/engagements in which one is simultaneously
listless in the current situation and restless to find relief from it.
Furthermore, I interpret boredom in terms of interaction withdrawal and claim
that it is relational in character, as it always emerges in the context of some
interplay between one’s personal attitude, perception, characteristics, etc.
and something external (activity, object, one’s social position, institutional
ambience, one’s life from which one is alienated, etc.). One’s relationship or
connection with other people, one’s environment, the performed task,
or—ultimately—with oneself, erodes. Thus, I argue that every manifestation
of boredom somehow breaks or ends an interaction; each case of boredom implies
its negligence. Frequently, such an emotion is just momentary, being quickly
replaced by other emotions—the relation with social/physical environment is
re-established and one is free from the sensation. This is why I have called it
‘a conveyor belt.’ A simple yet representative example of such a process is
students’ boredom during university classes. ‘Pure’ boredom (inattention and
lack of engagement, manifested by idleness, sleepiness, glazed look, supporting
one’s head with one’s elbow) appears there quite rarely, because students’
disengagement from the interaction with the teacher and with the content of the
course quickly becomes replaced by their engagement in alternative activities (Finkielsztein, 2013). In the
case where a student perceives particular classes as
personally meaningless, they disengage from them by directing their attention
to something else. In this sense, the student does not feel bored. All the
same, their boredom in class is dormant, latent—ready to erupt as soon as the
side engagement expires. There again, in my conceptualisation, it would not be
treated as boredom. To be more specific, I argue that one’s cognitive appraisal
that something is boring is not equivalent to feeling bored, but it constitutes
only one of the factors predictive of boredom. In brief, one is bored with a
boring activity only when they are actively ‘exposed’ to it. In this
connection, a student may attend a boring lecture and yet feel even excited in
class—because of them being absorbed in some non-class related, exciting
preoccupation during that time (see more in Finkielsztein,
2019).
I am
convinced that the above definition can have potentially universal
applicability. Firstly, if one is inattentive to the situation at hand and
disengaged from it, we call this ‘situational boredom’. Secondly, if the state
is recurrent, it can become transformed into a mood with the same qualities
and, accordingly, be called ‘chronic boredom.’ Thirdly, if it embraced one’s
life in general (one is disconnected/alienated from one’s life, which they
regard as meaningless), it would be called ‘existential boredom.’ Therefore,
depending on the scope of boredom occurrence in one’s life—from the most
limited to the broadest—different kinds of boredom may be distinguished. From
this perspective, situational and existential boredoms may be defined in terms
of generally analogous features (such as the sense of meaninglessness,
engagement withdrawal and listlessness/restlessness), but there is a crucial
difference which makes the two types of boredom clearly distinguishable. To be
specific, existential boredom is not a short-lived emotion/feeling but a mood,
which lasts usually for a longer period of time, is
low in intensity and is object-less/undirected (Thoits,
1989). It is rather a background sensation, or—as
Heidegger (1995) stated—rather a standpoint
colouring our perception of the reality. Somebody who suffers from existential
boredom (1) assesses their life, or life in general, as worthless, (2) lives
without much genuine involvement in it, and (3) is generally somewhat lethargic.
Nevertheless, they yearn for meaning—as it remains their point of reference and
something that they want to gain in life, even if not believing much in the
success of the pursuit.
6. Conclusions
It is certain that much
remains to be learned about boredom and that the presented analysis is not the
last word in the on-going discussion about its conceptualisation. Still, the
paper provides a novel approach to how to define it, which I hope proves to be
useful in further empirical studies of that emotion. The proposed conceptualisation
is based on interdisciplinary and thorough analysis of existing approaches and
summarises them in order to offer a multi-dimensional
definition which is meant to overcome disciplinary limitations of the previous
ones. It primarily attempts to include a sociological perspective on boredom
and challenge the domination of the domain by psychological perspectives, yet
simultaneously integrates these visions in the quest to identify the essence of
situational boredom. To better visualize the claims of the paper, I summarize
the main arguments in the table below (Table 1).
Table 1:
Non-Essential and Essential Elements in Defining Boredom
Non-Essential Elements |
|
1. Idleness/Low Arousal |
Boredom is not the situation
of having nothing to do but rather the feeling of having nothing worth doing.
Mere idleness could be cured by work/occupation, but the impressive bulk of
studies shows that vocational boredom is one of the major problems of modern
workplaces. Lack of stimulation, and a resulting low level of cortical
arousal, is not essential for boredom, as there are other affective states
also characterised by a low level of arousal (e.g. sadness, dejection,
laziness). |
2. Rest |
Contrarily to some
taken-for-granted views on boredom, it is not a form ‘mental relaxation’ as what proves crucial in defining
boredom is the subject’s negative perception of the feeling. The state of low
arousal and satisfaction constitutes a state of relaxation and peacefulness
that is qualitatively different than boredom, which take place when one is
inactive and, at the same time, does not want to stay inactive any longer. |
3. Laziness |
Laziness is rather one of
the possible outcomes of boredom or of its anticipation—one usually gets lazy
when they are not willing to do something that they expect to be boring,
unpleasant, difficult and/or wearisome. Laziness is not a part of boredom due
to its, well-proved restless component that pushes an individual out of their
laziness. |
4. Apathy |
Apathy entails total lack of
emotion, numbness, and lack of motivation to all stimuli; boredom increases
motivation for seeking alternative stimuli. Apathy is a more radical state,
whose scope, to some extent, may overlap that of boredom (in its listless
part) but lacks many other qualities of it. |
5. Repetition/Monotony |
The findings of a large number of studies indicate that repetitiveness does
not necessarily induce boredom: (a) some industrial workers even express a
preference for routine tasks, arguing that those provide them with an
opportunity to focus their thoughts elsewhere, typically on more pleasurable
activities. When, in the eyes of the person who has settled down into a
routine, it is meaningful and purposeful, the routine does not cause boredom
and may even provide them with a sense of security and belongingness.
Therefore, monotony is only one of the possible causes of boredom. |
6. Lack of Interest |
Lack of interest is
affectively neutral, implying neither the wish to engage in the situation at
hand nor the wish to escape from it, whereas boredom is clearly affectively
negative. One can feel disinterest in many topics, and it does not provoke
any affective reaction in them; they simply do not care about them. Boredom
constitutes rather a state of strong counterinterest. |
7. Slow Passage of Time |
In boredom, we are basically
unengaged, and we perceive more temporal pulses, because we more consciously
experience the passage of time. Consequently, the time seems to drag on. In
other words, when someone is not engaged in an activity, they allocate more
attentional resources to the passage of time, which creates the impression
that time is moving slowly. Thus, slow passage of time is rather a
consequence of boredom. |
Essential Elements |
|
1. Emotion/Feeling |
Boredom is almost
unanimously conceptualized as an emotion fitting nicely into the most common
definition of emotions. Boredom is a short-lived, subjective,
psycho-physiological affective state that can be described as having five
components: affective, physiological, cognitive, motivational, and
expressive. Emotions are generally conceived of as being unconscious, whereas
feelings constitute the conscious mode of an emotion, its extension towards
the realm of awareness. Boredom would be an emotion if unconscious, and a
feeling if conscious. |
2. Negativity/Aversion |
All existing literature
reviews shows that boredom is commonly perceived and conceptualized as an
aversive state. Yet, it is not negative (as it may serve various functions)
but rather negatively perceived as associated with the feeling of
dissatisfaction. |
3. Listlessness and Restlessness |
Boredom is characterised
simultaneously by listlessness and restlessness. Listlessness alone would
constitute the state of apathy, and restlessness merely a kind of
nervousness. On the one hand, there are innumerable testimonies
characterising boredom as a sort of freezing, weariness, lethargy, or lack of
care. On the other hand, boredom is connected with a
high motivation for stimulation, a constant search for novelty, and
agitation. Boredom implies a longing
to engage in an unspecified satisfying activity and a call to action.
To be bored, thus, is to experience listlessness and restlessness at the same
time, with the former being directed towards the situation at hand and the
latter being directed towards a prospective activity, specifically, escaping
from the anesthetising experience. |
4. Disengagement, Attention Withdrawal |
Boredom is primarily the
experience of disengagement from an interaction. This is the situation where
an individual experiences being disengaged from the human interaction and not
being involved in or engaged by events or activities. Essential for boredom
is some form of lack of engagement and withdrawal of attention (attentional
disengagement). It is a relational state characterised by lack of involvement
in any kind of social or non-social activity, neglect of or withdrawal from
active and genuine participation in interaction with other people or objects. |
5. Meaninglessness |
An atrophy of meaning, sense
of meaninglessness, specifically the subject’s personally-perceived lack of
meaning in a concrete situation—not general meaninglessness of some kind of
activity, is a distinctive and essential feature/cause of boredom. Boredom
constitutes a kind of meaning frustration, i.e., an emotional reaction to the
unfulfilled need for meaning or to the unsuccessful construction of meaning. |
6. Liminality, Transitionality |
Boredom is a state of being
stuck in-between, of suspension between engagements—one involvement has
ceased but another has not yet begun. Boredom is characteristic of any on-going
transitions that inhibit the process of becoming. A bored person is
imprisoned in a kind of limbo, stuck between activities, statuses,
experiences, or engagements. |
Source: collated by the author.
References
Aho, K.
(2007). Simmel on Acceleration, Boredom, and Extreme Aesthesia. Journal for
the Theory of Social Behaviour, 37(4), 447–462. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-5914.2007.00345.x
Baker, R., D’Mello,
S., Rodrigo, M. M., and Graesser, A. (2010). Better
to Be Frustrated than Bored: The Incidence, Persistence, and Impact of Learners’
Cognitive-Affective States During Interactions with Three Different Computer-based
Learning Environments. International Journal of Human Computer Studies, 68(4),
223–241.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijhcs.2009.12.003
Baratta,
P. (2014). The “Noonday Demon”, Weariness, Inattention, or All of the Above?
Refining the Definition and Measurement of State Boredom. MA Thesis, The
University of Guelph, Ontario, Canada.
Barbalet,
J. (1999). Boredom and Social Meaning. The British Journal of Sociology,
50(4), 631–646. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-4446.1999.00631.x
Bargdill,
R. (2000). A Phenomenological Investigation of Being Bored with Life. Psychological
Reports, 86(2), 493–494. https://doi.org/10.2466/pr0.2000.86.2.493
Bauman,
Z. (2000). Liquid Modernity. Polity Press.
Beckelman,
L. (1995). Boredom. Crestwood House.
Bench, S.,
and Lench,
H. (2013). On the Function of Boredom. Behavioral
Sciences, 3(3), 459–472. https://doi.org/10.3390/bs3030459
Benjamin,
W. (2007). The Storyteller. In Illuminations. Essays and Reflections on the
Works of Nikolai Leskov
(pp. 83–109). Schocken Books.
Beres,
D. (2017). Does Boredom Really Exist? Big Think. http://bigthink.com/21st-century-spirituality/does-boredom-exist
Berger,
P., and Luckmann,
T. (1991). The Social Construction of Reality. Penguin Books.
Bernstein,
H. (1975). Boredom and the Ready-made Life. Social Research, 42(3),
512–537.
Bibring,
E. (1953). The Mechanisms of Depression. In P. Greenacre (Ed.), Affective
Disorders (pp. 13–48). International Universities Press.
Brisset,
D., and Snow, R. (1993). Boredom: Where the Future Isn’t. Symbolic
Interaction, 16(3), 237–256.
Bruss, K.
(2012). Searching for Boredom in Ancient Greek Rhetoric: Clues in Isocrates. Philosophy
and Rhetoric, 45(3), 312–334. https://doi.org/10.5325/philrhet.45.3.0312
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.anbehav.2017.06.006
Chan, C., Van
Tilburg, W., Igou, E., Poon, C., Tam, K., Wong, V., and Cheung, S. K. (2018).
Situational Meaninglessness and State Boredom: Cross-sectional and Experience-sampling
Findings. Motivation and Emotion, 42(4), 555–565. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-018-9693-3
Chin, A.,
Markey, A., Bhargava, S., Kassam, K., and Loewenstein, G. (2017). Emotion Bored
in the USA: Experience Sampling and Boredom in Everyday Life. Emotion, 17(2),
359–368. https://doi.org/10.1037/emo0000232
Conrad,
P. (1997). It’s Boring: Notes on the Meanings of Boredom in Everyday Life. Qualitative
Sociology as Everyday Life, 20(4), 123–133. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1024747820595
Csikszentmihalyi,
M. (2000). Boredom. In A. Kazdin (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Psychology
(pp. 442–444). Oxford University Press.
Danckert, J., and Elpidorou, A. (2023). In Search of Boredom:
Beyond a Functional Account. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 27(5).
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2023.02.002
Danckert, J., Hammerschmidt, T., Marty-Dugas, J., and Smilek, D. (2018). Boredom: Under-aroused and Restless. Consciousness
and Cognition, 61, 24–37.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2018.03.014
Daschmann,
E., Goetz, T., and Stupnisky, R. (2011). Testing the Predictors
of Boredom at School: Development and Validation of the Precursors to Boredom Scales.
The British Journal of Educational Psychology, 81(3), 421–440. https://doi.org/10.1348/000709910X526038
de Chenne, T. (1998). Boredom as a Clinical Issue. Psychotherapy: Theory, Research, Practice, Training, 25(1), 71–81. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/h0085325
de la Peña, A. (2006). Consequences of
Increments in Cognitive Structure for Attentional Automatization, the
Experience of Boredom, and Engagement in Egocentric, Hyperdynamic, Interest-generating
Behaviors: A Developmental Psychophysiologic
Approach. Proceedings of the 50th Annual Meeting of the ISSS –
2006, Sonoma, CA, USA.
de
Musset, A. (2006). Confession of a Child of the Century. Project
Gutenberg.
Digitales
Wörterbuch der deutschen Sprache. (n.d.). Langeweile. DWDS.
https://www.dwds.de/wb/Langeweile
Drory,
A. (1982). Individual Differences in Boredom Proneness and Task Effectiveness
at Work. Personnel Psychology, 35(1), 141–152. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1744-6570.1982.tb02190.x
Eastwood,
J., Frischen,
A., Fenske, M., and Smilek, D. (2012). The Unengaged
Mind: Defining Boredom in Terms of Attention. Perspectives on Psychological
Science, 7(5), 482–495. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691612456044
Elpidorou, A. (2016). The Benefits of Boredom [Video]. Creative
Mornings HQ.
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Gui2vznOvj8
Elpidorou, A. (2017a). The Bored Mind Is a Guiding Mind: Toward a Regulatory Theory
of Boredom. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(3),
455–484.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9515-1
Elpidorou, A. (2017b). The Moral Dimensions of Boredom: A Call for Research. Review
of General Psychology, 21(1), 30–48. https://doi.org/10.1037/gpr0000098
Elpidorou, A. (2021). Is Boredom One or Many? A Functional Solution to the Problem
of Heterogeneity. Mind & Language, 36(3), 491–511. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12282
Fahlman, S., Mercer, K., Gaskovski, P., Eastwood, A., and Eastwood, J.
(2009). Does a Lack of Life Meaning Cause Boredom? Results from Psychometric,
Longitudinal, and Experimental Analyses. Journal of Social and Clinical
Psychology, 28(3), 307–340.
https://doi.org/10.1521/jscp.2009.28.3.307
Fahlman, S., Mercer-Lynn, K., Flora, D., and Eastwood, J. (2013).
Development and Validation of the Multidimensional State Boredom Scale. Assessment,
20(1), 68–85.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1073191111421303
Fenichel,
O. (1951). On the Psychology of Boredom. In Organization and Pathology of Thought
(pp. 349–361). Columbia University Press.
Finkielsztein, M. (2013). Nuda Na Zajęciach
Uniwersyteckich. Percepcja Nudy Wśród Studentów Uniwersytetu Warszawskiego
[Boredom During University Classes. The Perception of Boredom Among Students of the
University of Warsaw]. MA Thesis, The
University of Warsaw, Poland.
Finkielsztein, M. (2018). Nuda a lenistwo, gnuśność i acedia [Boredom and Laziness, Sloth, and Acedia]. Maska,
37, 36–50.
Finkielsztein, M. (2019). On the Social
Significance of Boredom. The Phenomenon of Boredom in the University Milieu.
PhD Thesis, The University of Warsaw, Poland.
Finkielsztein, M. (2021). Boredom and Academic
Work. Routledge.
Fisher, C. (1987). Boredom: Construct, Causes and
Consequences [Report]. Texas A&M University/Virginia
Polytechnic Institute.
Fisher,
C. (1993). Boredom at Work: A Neglected Concept. Human Relations, 46(3),
395–417.
Frankl,
V. (2000). Man’s Search for Meaning. An Introduction to Logotherapy.
Beacon Press.
Frederiksen,
M. (2017). Joyful Pessimism: Marginality, Disengagement, and the Doing of Nothing.
Focaal, 78, 9–22. https://doi.org/10.3167/fcl.2017.780102
Frijda,
N. (1986). The Emotions. Cambridge University Press.
Fromm, E.
(2002). The Sane Society. Routledge.
Gabelman,
D. (2010). Bubbles, Butterflies and Bores: Play and Boredom in Don Juan.
The Byron Journal, 38(2), 145–156. https://doi.org/10.3828/bj.2010.23
Gardiner, M.
(2014). The Multitude Strikes Back? Boredom in an Age of Eemiocapitalism.
New Formations: A Journal of Culture/Theory/Politics, 82(82),
29–46.
https://doi.org/10.3898/NEWF.82.02.2014
Giakoumis,
D., Tzovaras, D., Moustakas, K., and Hassapis, G. (2011). Automatic Recognition of Boredom in Video
Games Using Novel Biosignal Moment-based Features. IEEE
Transactions on Affective Computing, 2(3), 119–133. https://doi.org/10.1109/T-AFFC.2011.4
Goetz, T.,
Frenzel,
A., Hall, N., Nett, U., Pekrun, R., and Lipnevich, A. (2014). Types of Boredom: An Experience Sampling
Approach. Motivation and Emotion, 38(3), 401–419. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-013-9385-y
Goffman,
E. (1982). Interaction Ritual; Essays on Face-to-face Behavior.
Pantheon Books.
Greenson,
R. (1953). On Boredom. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association,
1, 7–21.
Gurycka, A.
(1977). Przeciw nudzie. O aktywności [Against Boredom. On Activity]. Nasza Księgarnia.
Harris, M. (2000). Correlates
and Characteristics of Boredom Proneness and Boredom. Journal of Applied
Social Psychology, 30(3), 576–598.
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1559-1816.2000.tb02497.x
Healy, S.
D. (1984). Boredom, Self, and Culture. Fairleigh Dickenson University
Press.
Helvétius,
C. A. (1810). De l'Esprit; or, Essays on the Mind and Its Several Faculties.
Albion Press.
Hill, A.
(1975). Work Variety and Individual Differences in Occupational Boredom. Journal
of Applied Psychology, 60(1), 128–131. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0076346
Hill,
A., and Perkins, R. (1985). Towards a Model of Boredom. British Journal of
Psychology, 76, 235–240. https://doi.org/http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.2044-8295.1985.tb01947.x
Irvine,
I. (2001). The Angel of Luxury and Sadness. Vol. 1: The Emergence of the
Normative Ennui Cycle. BookSurge
Publishing.
Jaucourt,
C. de (1772). Ennui. In D. Diderot (Ed.), Encyclopedie,
ou Dictionnaire-Raisonné
des Sciences, des Arts et des Métiers. Wikisource.
Jeronimus,
B., and Laceulle, O. (2017). Frustration. In V.
Zeigler-Hill and T. Shackelford (Eds.), Encyclopedia
of Personality and Individual Differences (pp. 1–5). Springer.
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28099-8
Jervis,
L., Spicer, P., and Hanson, S. (2003). Boredom, “Trouble,” and the Realities of
Postcolonial Reservation Life. Ethos, 31(1),
38–58. https://doi.org/10.1525/eth.2003.31.1.38
Kabzińska,
K. (2015). Nuda w kulturze nadmiaru [Boredom in a
Culture of Excess]. MA Thesis, Uniwersytet im. Adama Mickiewicza w Poznaniu,
Poland.
Kenny, L.
(2009). Boredom Escapes Us: A Cultural Collage in Eleven Storeys.
University of Toronto.
Kierkegaard,
S. (1843). Either/Or. Squashed Philosophers.
Kirova,
A. (2004). Lonely or Bored: Children’s Lived Experiences Reveal the Difference.
Interchange, 35(2), 243–268. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02698852
Klapp,
O. (1986). Overload and Boredom. Essays on the Quality of Life in the
Information Society. Greenwood Press.
Krasicki, I.
(1994). Pan Podstoli [Mr.
Podstoli]. Wyższa Szkoła Pedagogiczna.
Kuhn, R. (1976). The
Demon of Noontide. Ennui in Western Literature.
Princeton University Press.
Laird, J.
(2007). Feelings: The Perception of Self. Oxford University Press.
London,
H., and Monello,
L. (1974). Cognitive Manipulation of Boredom. In H. London and R. Nisbett
(Eds.), Thought and Feeling: Cognitive Alteration of Feeling States (pp.
74–84). Aldine.
Loukidou,
L., Loan-Clarke, J., and Daniels, K. (2009). Boredom in the Workplace: More
than Monotonous Tasks. International Journal of Management Reviews, 11(4),
381–405.
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2370.2009.00267.x
MacDonald,
D., and Holland, D. (2002). Spirituality and Boredom Proneness. Personality
and Individual Differences, 32(6), 1113–1119. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0191-8869(01)00114-3
Macklem,
G. (2015). Boredom in the Classroom. Addressing Student Motivation, Self-regulation,
and Engagement in Learning. Springer.
Mael, F., and Jex,
S. (2015). Workplace Boredom: An Integrative Model of Traditional and
Contemporary Approaches. Group & Organization Management, 40(2),
131–159.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1059601115575148
Maltsberger, J. (2000). Case Consultation: Mansur Zaskar: A Man Almost Bored to Death.
Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 30(1),
83–90.
Mansikka,
J. E. (2009). Can Boredom Educate Us? Tracing a Mood in Heidegger’s Fundamental
Ontology from an Educational Point of View. Studies in Philosophy and
Education, 28(3), 255–268. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-008-9116-0
Markowski,
M. P. (1999). L'Ennui.
Ułamek historii [Boredom. A Fraction
of History]. In Nuda w kulturze (pp. 290–316).
Rebis.
Martin,
M., Sadlo,
G., and Stew, G. (2006). The Phenomenon of Boredom. Qualitative Research in
Psychology, 3, 193–211. https://doi.org/10.1139/b87-051
Marx, K.
(1992). Early Writings. Penguin Books.
Merriam-Webster (n.d.). Boredom. Merriam-Webster.
https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/boredom
Merriam-Webster (2004). Webster’s
Student Dictionary. International Encyclopedic
Edition. Bellavista.
Meyer, C. (n.d.). Emotions versus
Feelings. The Emotional Detective.
http://emotionaldetective.typepad.com/EMOTIONAL-DETECTIVE/2012/04/EMOTIONS-VS-FEELINGS.HTML
Meyer Spacks, P. (1995). Boredom: The Literary
History of a State of Mind. Chicago University Press.
Mijuskovic,
B. (1979). Loneliness in Philosophy, Psychology, and Literature. Van Gorcum.
Mikulas,
W., and Vodanovich, S. (1993). The Essence of Boredom. Psychological Record,
43(1), 237–247. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11606-012-2196-0
Misztal,
B. (2016). The Ambiguity of Everyday Experience: Between Normality and Boredom.
Qualitative Sociology Review, 12(4), 100–119. https://doi.org/10.18778/1733-8077.12.4.06
Mosurinjohn, S. (2016). Overload, Boredom and the Aesthetics of Texting. In M.
Gardiner and J. J. Haladyn (Eds.), Boredom Studies
Reader (pp. 143–156). Routledge.
Mulligan,
K., and Scherer, K. (2012). Toward a Working Definition of Emotion. Emotion
Review, 4(4), 345–357. https://doi.org/10.1177/1754073912445818
Musharbash,
Y. (2007). Boredom, Time, and Modernity: An Example from Aboriginal Australia. American
Anthropologist, 109(2), 307–317. https://doi.org/10.1525/AA.2007.109.2.307.308
Ngai, S.
(2005). Ugly Feelings. Harvard University Press.
O’Brien,
W. (2014). Boredom. Analysis, 74(2), 236–244. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anu041
O’Hanlon,
J. (1981). Boredom: Practical Consequences and a Theory. Acta Psychologica,
49(1), 53–82. https://doi.org/10.1016/0001-6918(81)90033-0
O’Neill,
B. (2014). Cast Aside: Boredom, Downward Mobility, and Homelessness in
Post-Communist Bucharest. Cultural Anthropology, 29(1), 8–31. https://doi.org/10.14506/ca29.1.03
Pessoa,
F. (2002). The Book of Disquiet. Penguin Books.
Preckel,
F., Götz, T., and Frenzel,
A. (2010). Ability Grouping of Gifted Students: Effects on
Academic Self-concept and Boredom. British Journal of Educational Psychology,
80, 451–472. https://doi.org/10.1348/000709909X480716
Prinz, J.
(2005). Are Emotions Feelings? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12(8–10),
9–25.
Raposa,
M. (1999). Boredom and the Religious Imagination. University Press of
Virginia.
Rogge, B. (2011). Boredom, the Life Course, and Late Modemity. Understanding Subjectivity and Sociality of “Dead Time” Experiences. BIOS, 24, 284–299.
Ros Velasco, J. (2022). La enfermedad del aburrimiento [The Disease of Boredom]. Alianza.
Ros
Velasco, J. (2023). Contemporary Myths on Boredom. Frontiers in Sociology,
8.
https://doi.org/10.3389/fsoc.2023.1183875
Rothlin,
P., and Werder, P. (2008). Boreout!
Overcoming Workplace Demotivation. Page.
Safranski,
R. (2015). Zeit, was sie mit uns macht und was wir aus ihr
machen [Time, What It Does
to Us and What We Make of It]. Hanser.
Sandywell,
B. (2016). The Dialectic of Lassitude: A Reflexive Investigation. In M.
Gardiner and J. J. Haladyn (Eds.), Boredom Studies
Reader (pp. 38–52). Routledge.
Sartre,
J.-P. (1962). Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Methuen & Co Ltd.
Saunders,
M. N. (1996). The Physiology of Boredom, Depression and Senile Dementia. Medical
Hypotheses, 46(5), 463–466. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0306-9877(96)90026-2
Schielke,
S. (2008). Boredom and Despair in Rural Egypt. Contemporary Islam, 2(3),
251–270. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11562-008-0065-8
Sontag,
S. (1967). Against Interpretation. Dell Publishing.
Steiner,
G. (1971). The Great Ennui. In In Bluebeard’s Castle: Some Notes Towards the
Redefinition of Culture (pp. 1–26). Yale University Press.
Strelau, J., and
Doliński, D. (Eds.). (2011). Psychologia
akademicka. Podręcznik, tom 1 [Academic Psychology. Manual, Vol. 1]. Gdańskie Wydawnictwo Psychologiczne.
Struk,
A., Scholer, A., and Danckert,
J. (2021). Perceptions of Control Influence Feelings of Boredom. Frontier in
Psychology, 12. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2021.687623
Svendsen,
L. (2005). A Philosophy of Boredom. Reaktion Books.
Svendsen,
L. (2016). Boredom and the Meaning of Life. In M. Gardiner and J. J. Haladyn
(Eds.), Boredom Studies Reader (pp. 205–215). Routledge.
Szymczak, M.
(Ed.). (1995). Słownik Języka Polskiego, tom 2 L-P [Polish Dictionary, Vol. 2 L-P].
PWN.
Tam, K., Van
Tilburg, W., Chan, C., Igou, E., and Lau, H. (2021). Attention Drifting in and
out: The Boredom Feedback Model. Personality and Social Psychology Review,
25(3), 251–272. https://doi.org/10.1177/10888683211010297
Thiele,
L. P. (1997). Postmodernity and the Routinization of Novelty:
Heidegger on Boredom and Technology. Polity, 29(4), 489–517.
Thoits,
P. (1989). The Sociology of Emotions. Annual Review of Sociology, 15(1),
317–342. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511819612
Todman,
M. (2003). Boredom and Psychotic Disorders: Cognitive and Motivational Issues. Psychiatry,
66(2), 146–167. https://doi.org/10.1521/psyc.66.2.146.20623
Toohey,
P. (2011). Boredom: A Lively History. Yale University Press.
Van Gennep, A. (1960). The Rites of Passage.
Chicago University Press.
Van Hooff,
M., and Van Hooft, E. (2014). Boredom at Work: Proximal and Distal
Consequences of Affective Work-related Boredom. Journal of Occupational
Health Psychology, 19(3), 348–359. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0036821
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-011-9234-9
Vogel-Walcutt,
J., Fiorella, L., Carper, T., and Schatz, S. (2012).
The Definition, Assessment, and Mitigation of State Boredom Within Educational
Settings: A Comprehensive Review. Educational Psychology Review, 24(1),
89–111. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10648-011-9182-7
Voltaire
(2006). Candide. Oxford University Press.
Wagner,
I. (2015). Producing Excellence: The Making of Virtuosos. Rutgers
University Press.
Wechter-Ashkin,
L. (2010). The College Freshman’s Lived Experience of Boredom: A
Phenomenological Study. Capella University.
https://doi.org/10.1037/rev0000097
Wilcock,
A. (2006). An Occupational Perspective of Health. Slack.
Wolff, W.,
Radtke,
V., and Martarelli, C. (2022). Same but Different –
What Is Boredom Actually? PsyArXiv
Preprints. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/jze5k
Zakay,
D. (2014). Psychological Time as Information: The Case of Boredom. Frontiers
in Psychology, 5(August), 1–5. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00917
Zhu, B., and Zhou, Y.
(2012). A Study on Students’ Affective Factors in Junior High School English Teaching.
English Language Teaching, 5(7), 33–41. https://doi.org/10.5539/elt.v5n7p33
[1] The article is a re-edited and
updated version of Chapter 3 (pp. 69–80) of my book Boredom
and Academic Work (Routledge, 2021).
[2] The body analyzed included 397
articles (25 in Polish and 372 in English), 29 books (5 in Polish and 24 in
English), 90 chapters in books (33 in Polish and 57 in English), and 31
master’s and doctoral dissertations (2 in Polish and 29 in English).