Journal of Boredom
Studies (ISSN 2990-2525)
Issue 1, 2023, pp. 1–23
https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.7603687
https://www.boredomsociety.com/jbs
Aesthetic Boredom in Everyday Architecture
Abel B. Franco
California State
University
How to cite this paper: Franco, A. B. (2023). Aesthetic
Boredom in Everyday Architecture. Journal of Boredom Studies, 1. https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.7603687
Abstract: I defend that saying in everyday parlance that an
architectonic space is ‘boring’ can be an aesthetic judgement and, in such
cases, we can talk about a form of aesthetic boredom about spaces. As
an emotion (rather than a mood), aesthetic boredom would be the negative or
opposite emotion to what might be called our aesthetic excitement about
a space. The latter would be our emotional response to what I call the
aesthetic quality of inhabitability: the
quality of a space which we experience as being responsible for 1) creating
possibilities which are significant for us (regarding what we can do and how we
can do it in that space), and for 2) enhancing (qualitatively) the experience
of realizing those possibilities. Unlike (simple) boredom about a space,
aesthetic boredom would be boredom due primarily to the absence of inhabitability thus understood. As to the frustrated
desire which, as it is commonly understood, is constitutive of boredom, I will
argue that this desire is the one revealed by our constant active search for inhabitability in the spaces in which we
find ourselves, or for greater inhabitability when we choose them. Our
frustration is a response, not simply to not encountering possibilities, but
rather, to realizing that there are none where we expect some. This would
explain the considerable strength of our (negative) response to boring spaces.
We experience aesthetically boring spaces as spaces that deny both significant possibilities and the enhancement of the felt quality
of the experience of realizing them.
Keywords: boredom, aesthetics, architecture,
inhabitability, spaces, aesthetic boredom.
1. Introduction
I defend here that we
can talk about a form of aesthetic boredom distinctive of our everyday
experience of architectonic spaces, that is, distinctive of our experience of
using man-made spaces as we go about our daily life. This aesthetic boredom is
an affective response that seems to exhibit the
defining features of the common experience of boredom while being specifically
about an aesthetic quality of spaces. I will also try to show that this
experience meets the general requirements to be considered an emotion.[1]
Affective experiences imply valuing; aesthetic
appreciation implies aesthetic valuing. As both an affective and
aesthetic experience, the task I propose requires paying particular attention
to what we value in each case, that is, to the intentional object of our
everyday experience.[2] In
this case, this means paying attention to what exactly our aesthetic boredom
towards a space is about—as opposed to an objectless boredom, or to our
(simple) boredom about a space, or to our aesthetic appreciation of a
space.
I will propose to understand aesthetic boredom about
spaces as our affective response to the absence of an aesthetic quality that I
take to be distinctive of spaces, namely, the quality I call inhabitability.
In this precise sense, inhabitability is the quality of a space which we
experience as being responsible for 1) creating possibilities significant for
us regarding what we can do and how we can do it (in that space), and for 2)
enhancing the felt quality of the experience of realizing those possibilities
(in that space). Aesthetic boredom would result from the clash between our
always-present desire for inhabitability—whose existence I will also defend—and
its absence in the space we are currently filling (or occupying).
Since I am attempting to explain everyday experience, I
will study it as it can be observed primarily via phenomenological
analysis of our own experiences, and via behaviors and common linguistic
expressions when it comes to third parties. The goal is to show that the
everyday experience that accompanies our judgments of—or thoughts, or behaviors
indicating it—architectonic structures as ‘boring’ can be cases of aesthetic
boredom about spaces. In these cases, 1) the judgements (or behaviors)
accompanying the experience are about our everyday use of architecture qua
architecture (i.e., about architecture qua created spaces); 2) our
experience is both affective (in particular, proper of an emotion) and aesthetic,
and 3) it results from the frustrated desire to find the distinctive aesthetic
quality of spaces in the space we are occupying.
I will undertake mainly three tasks to show this. First,
I will try to demarcate the experience I am referring to by addressing
the when (we have this experience). Second, I will bring into the
argument—in order to identify the sense in which we can talk about an aesthetic
experience—the view I defended somewhere else (Franco, 2019) that the distinctive aesthetic object of our everyday experience of
architecture is the created space (as opposed to any perceivable feature
or object) and, more precisely, the aesthetic quality I call inhabitability.
This should explain both the phrase ‘qua architecture’ above and why we
can talk about an aesthetic emotion about architecture and how we should
understand it. And third, I will try to show that the aesthetic experience that
we can call everyday aesthetic boredom about spaces seems to have all the
defining components—on which there is considerable agreement among
researchers (Scherer, 1984)—of the affective experiences that
we call emotions.[3]
2. Boring Spaces
2.1. Experiencing a Boring
Space
We want to understand
everyday experiences in which built environments produce the type of response
we ordinarily express by declaring those environments ‘boring’ or, more
precisely, by declaring (or meaning) that the spaces they create are ‘boring’
or that ourselves are ‘bored’ by them. In general, we think of something as
boring when we take it to produce boredom in us or, probably more frequently,
if we perceive it may contribute to produce it. “To be boring is to tend
to bore” (O’Brien, 2014, p. 238); “boring” is that which
“annoys, wearies, or causes ennui” (Oxford English Dictionary, 2022c). A boring space would then be, in principle, one that has
boredom-inducing qualities.
As our experience shows, and this is one of the issues
this paper must explain, a space may be boring for some but not for
others (“anything could in principle for someone or other be an object of
boredom” [O’Brien, 2014, p. 241]). Although, as I will try
to show, we all perceive some common quality in the spaces we consider boring,
we do not all perceive that quality in the same spaces (“boredom is a hybrid,
partly objective, partly subjective” [Heidegger, 1995, p. 88]).
This means that it is difficult, if not impossible, to provide specific
examples of spaces which might be universally (experienced as) boring. An empty
factory building, a prison cell, a landfill, a parking lot, a hospital room, a
public restroom, a street where all the houses look alike, or an urban space
where all we can find is warehouses or storage structures could be, under
certain circumstances and for some, examples of either boring spaces or spaces
with boring features. The pictures under the title “Beautifully Boring Pictures
of Typical American Architecture” in Dundon (2016) or “Boring Urban Landscapes” in Ward (2012) or a
number of those in Preissner (2021a) could suggest more precise examples.
So, first, what is distinctive of the experience of
boredom in general? According to Elpidorou (2017a):
As a state
[“not the personality trait of boredom”], boredom is a concrete and short-lived
affective experience that is characterized by feelings
of dissatisfaction, attentional difficulties, and the perception of
meaninglessness. In a state of boredom, one is disengaged with one's
situation, and one wishes to do something else. Recent work on boredom suggests
that boredom is an emotion with a self-regulatory function. Because of its
affective, cognitive, and volitional character, boredom can motivate the pursuit
of a new goal when the current goal ceases to be attractive, meaningful, or
satisfactory.
According
to O’Brien (2014, p. 237), boredom is “a mental
state of weariness, restlessness, and lack of interest in something to which
one is subjected, which is unpleasant or undesirable, in which the weariness
and restlessness are causally related to the lack of interest”.
Notice
that, according to Elpidorou (2017a)’s definition “one is disengaged with one’s
situation”, which seems to imply that boredom about an object might not
be proper boredom. This is in consonance with our ordinary experiences and
language. ‘I am bored’ expresses my overall current affective ‘state’; ‘this
living room is boring’ does not (even if it is boring to me). According
to O’Brien, however, boredom implies “lack of interest in something to which
one is subjected”, where “something” can go from an “easily identifiable
object” to “your life” and “there always is an object of some sort that can be identified”
(2014, p. 241).
In
our case, although we are supposedly referring to an object (space), it
appears that the boredom we are dealing with here—aesthetic boredom about
spaces—could be a form of what Svendsen
(2005, p. 21) has called “situative
boredom”, which is “boredom that is due to something specific in a situation”,
as opposed to “existential boredom” which “affects [someone’s] existence as a
whole” (p. 42).[4]
We can be
bored with objects and people, we can be bored with
ourselves. But an anonymous form of boredom also exists where nothing in particular bores us. One feels
bored, for boredom does not have any content that can make it mine (Svendsen, 2005,
p. 41).
The “situation”
in question, in our case, would be distinctively defined by our
simultaneous experiences of 1) occupying and 2) evaluating
aesthetically a space (in an everyday manner). But this also means that 3)
any personal circumstances that affect the formation of these experiences can
be said to be part of the (lived) situation. The “something specific” to which
our boredom is “due”—if by this we mean caused—would be the space, or
some quality in it (if we accept that the perception of its intentional object
can be considered the prominent cause of an emotion).[5]
Notice that we are evaluating it aesthetically, even if such an evaluation is
done in a distracted and not very conscious fashion. We start evaluating a new
café as soon as we enter it and continue evaluating it for as long we are in it; we start evaluating a train station as
soon as we leave the train, and continue evaluating it as we walk through it
towards the exit.
We
can now return to the meaning of ‘boring’, that is, the (causally) active
meaning derived from ‘to bore’ and applied to objects. Do ‘boring’ objects
really produce boredom? ‘Boring’ objects seem to be experienced, rather than as
full-fledged boredom with its own course and temporal duration (proper of an affective response), as if they produced a lesser or
partial boredom. They seem to be experienced as if the boredom they
cause occurred primarily at the level of sensible perception, that
is, as what we could call visual or auditory or gustative-olfactory
or tactile boredom. Boring clothes or a boring meal or a boring
perfume seem to be of this kind. ‘Peter is wearing boring clothes’ does not
mean ‘I experience boredom when I see Peter wearing those clothes’; and ‘this
food is boring’ does not mean ‘I am bored when I am eating this food’.[6] We
rather mean that the sensible features of the object in question do not have
much interest—they are dull, plain, unexciting—and that this lack of interest
is of the sort that can produce an affective effect on us that we experience as
somehow similar or related to boredom. And it can produce this
effect precisely because, for some reason, we are paying attention to that
object (“lack of interest in something to which one is subjected” which
produces “weariness and restlessness” [O’Brien, 2014, p. 241]).
The above
‘somehow similar or related to’ suggests a relation similar
to the one between other emotional qualities we attribute to objects and
the experience of the emotion itself, e.g., a sad sunset, a joyful lamp, a
peaceful color.[7]
Notice, however, that, among the objects we may be more inclined to perceive as
emotional, spaces occupy a prominent place. We talk about a melancholic city, a
joyful café, or a serene poppy field. This seems to suggest that the emotion in
question might be more clearly experienced—i.e., it might retain more of its
features—when it is about these objects (spaces). Even so, the boredom
conveyed by a ‘boring’ space—or any other object for that matter—may not be as
clearly experienced as the one we attribute to activities in which we are
engaged. Unlike our sensorial exposure to boring objects, the experiences of
listening to a boring talk, or reading a boring book, or watching a boring
movie seem to be closer to what the active sense of ‘boring’ denotes. An
activity, especially if it requires our full attention, a considerable amount
of time, and it is one we have not chosen, is more likely to contribute to
produce boredom in us. Similarly, we are also more inclined to attribute
boredom-inducing capabilities to a space if, besides its boring appearance, we
must spend a considerable amount of time in it, or, more so, if we must spend
it doing activities we have not chosen.
Even
if we think about architectonic spaces as objects, they are
peculiar ones. A boring space and a boring car qualify the meaning of ‘boring’
in different ways. If we think in terms of what we can call the potential impact
of their boringness in our overall affective state, in both
cases—space and car—we can think about this impact as being compatible with a
simultaneous lack of boredom about other objects or even about the ‘situation’
as a whole. We can occupy a boring space and yet not be bored; we can see or
drive a boring car and not be bored. On the other hand, unlike a boring car,
the boringness of a space shares more closely similarities with the
boredom about a ‘situation’ than with the boredom about individual objects (if
by this we mean a well-delimited individual concrete thing). Our relation to
a space has more in common with our relation to a situation than with our
relation to an object per se. And the fact that we are immersed
in both could explain why a space or a situation may affect us more profoundly
than most ordinary boring objects—i.e., why they might be better carriers of
affective powers.
Boredom
about a space is, thus, different from boredom about individual objects, or
about particular experiences or activities. It is also different from general
states of boredom not caused by the external reality (or by a particular
activity)—i.e., from what Svendsen calls “existential boredom” (2005, p. 42). Boredom about spaces, on one hand, is
boredom that seems to have an external cause and yet differs from the
boredom—or the boringness—we attribute to individual concrete objects
(e.g., a table, a jacket); and, on the other, shares similarities with boredom
about particular activities (e.g., reading a book, watching a movie) without
being about an activity (at least, as we usually understand them). This could
be so both because spaces may not be proper objects or, if they are, we do not
experience them as such; and because, although we do not usually think of
spaces as activities, we experience them through actions. Let us turn to this
issue.
2.1. The Intentional Object:
Spaces, Not Physical Objects
Perceiving an
architectonic structure qua (physical) object tout court and
perceiving that structure qua space-creating or space-shaping
object are different things. Although both can be considered manners of
perceiving architecture, whereas the latter is distinctive of architecture, the
former is not (Franco, 2019). The creation or formation of spaces
to live (i.e., to realize human activities) defines and distinguishes
architecture from other creative activities. Other activities that may arguably
contribute to create space, such as furnishing or interior design, can be seen
as part of ‘architecture’ broadly understood. In any case, more important for
the purposes of this paper is that our everyday aesthetic evaluations of
architecture differ from the aesthetic evaluation of other objects and
activities in that they are primarily evaluations of created spaces (to live).[8]
Among the common expressions with which we affirm something
to be boring, when it comes to architectonic structures—or built
environments—our ordinary language is quite ambiguous regarding the precise
(intentional) object of our affective state. We do not usually say, or have an
expression that unequivocally says, something of the sort: ‘I feel
aesthetically bored by this city’, or better, ‘by this city’s space’. We rather
say simply ‘this city is boring’ or ‘this café is boring’. These expressions,
however, do not necessarily refer to the (created) space or to its aesthetic
value. They can refer to—and usually refer primarily to—the life, or
what we colloquially call the atmosphere, of that city or that café. And even
if they refer to the city or the café qua architecture, we can
understand this reference in two possible manners: 1) to the physical object(s)
or features we perceive through the senses (walls, floors, ceilings, furniture,
light, colors, textures, smells, etc.), or 2) to the space formed or shaped
by those physical objects and features—i.e., the city space or the café space
in this case.
Our ordinary language, once again, hides rather than
reveals the latter distinction. If we asked someone why they liked the café where
they had coffee yesterday, the answer will quite likely acquire the form of a
series of descriptions of pleasant physical things (e.g., chairs, tables,
decoration, light, colors, materials) interspersed, possibly, with some
references to the atmosphere (i.e., feelings perceived in, or generated by, the
café). So, how can we tell whether our
boredom is about the space itself? Can we tell apart our experience of boredom
about a space from boredom about the physical elements or features we perceive
around ourselves (when we occupy a space)?
Since we perceive the space we occupy, at least in part, from
the perception of the surrounding physical objects and their sensible
features, we should expect both perceptions (space and objects) to be narrowly
entangled in our experience. But this does not mean we cannot distinguish both
types of perceptions. Perceiving space, I suggest, is to perceive
possibilities for action (for the perceiver) created by the physical
interruptions (materials and their qualities, e.g., tables, walls,
decorations, sensible features) which can be encountered by our perceptual
reach and by our mobility and within which we are situated. Those ‘interruptions’
are such in relation to an empty or uninterrupted space. Placing a table
in a room is adding a physical interruption: it interrupts our sensible (mainly
visual) field and, potentially, our movements. And, thus, it creates and
eliminates possibilities for action (e.g., we can eat on it; we cannot walk
through it).
Although in certain circumstances we may not notice or
pay attention, we certainly cannot say we perceive these (material)
interruptions without perceiving their sensorial qualities (we see the wooden
tables, light-brown chairs, rugged tiles, and we feel the hard
floor and the sound of our steps on the floor). We manifest the
significance of these perceptions for us as we commonly attempt to alter our
living spaces by altering surrounding physical features (e.g., McKeough, 2022). And we do not perceive these features or sensorial qualities without
perceiving the (very personal) meaning they acquire under our gaze (cf.
Johnson, 2007). The leather armchair between the
old bronze floor reading lamp and the chimney, together with the dark wooden
bookshelves from floor to ceiling and the also wooden floor partially covered
by thick dark rugs means coziness. And, thus, they create—or contribute
to it—a cozy space. The space seems to borrow meaning from what we perceive.
Altering what we perceive sensorially alters the meaning
of the space via a sort of creation or transference of meaning
that seems to have its unique expression—or, at least, a breeding ground—in
spaces. This seems to occur as the very qualities we perceive in objects expand
or spread through space. ‘The cathedral smells like candles’ means ‘the
cathedral space smells like candles’; ‘the late-afternoon winter light
fills the library’ means ‘the late-afternoon winter light spreads through
the library space’. The concept of ecstasies, as Böhme
(1993) uses it, gives, a possible explanation of how
physical qualities qualify space and, thus, how this qualified space
triggers emotional responses (‘solemn atmosphere’; ‘cold atmosphere’).[9]
Similarly, if some of the surrounding physical features
appear to us as boring, they can make us perceive boringness in the
space. But this does not need to imply that perceiving boring features is perceiving
a boring space or even that perceiving boring features always make us perceive
a boring space. An empty apartment room—which might be the prototype of a
boring space for some—might exhibit boring features but not appear as a boring
space. The combination of its light, its size, and its shape might reveal a
potentially interesting (i.e., exciting to some degree) space. Even if
we might not be able to point out many non-boring features in a space (e.g., a
living room, a kitchen) we may freely choose to occupy it regularly. It is
possible, then, to think about features which might be boring if taken
individually but that do not create a boring space—or which, precisely because
they seem to contribute to create a (non-boring) space, they may acquire a
not-so-boring appearance.
When it comes to evaluating spaces—as opposed to
simply perceiving them—a reliable test to determine whether we are
evaluating what we perceive through the senses or the space itself might be our
own behavior. We experience—and judge—spaces while we do things in them, that
is, as we actively occupy and fill them with our physical presence and life. If
our choice is free, we choose between spaces primarily depending on how we feel
in them—i.e., how we feel ourselves occupying and filling them—which means
how we feel in them as we do something in them. And how we feel in them
depends on our perception of their inhabitability as defined above.
This means that neither our senses nor the
function of the space has primacy in determining our free choices. We often
spend more time or do more things—all things being equal and assuming, once
again, we are choosing freely—in spaces in which we would not say that
what we see, touch, smell, or hear is more pleasurable. The latter might be
relevant but not determining. Our preference is not determined either by the
functionality, narrowly understood, of the architectonic structure. It is true
that, as we choose one among several structures for a certain activity, we
usually do not even take into account those structures
in which we cannot realize that activity. But all things being equal and our
choices being free, we often prefer spaces that have less functionality with
respect to the activity we want to realize. We often prefer to write a paper in
the old library instead of in our own kitchen despite not having outlets for
computers, being noisier, colder, and with harder seats. When we choose freely,
our preference is for spaces with greater inhabitability. I turn to this
now.
3. Aesthetic Boredom
3.1. When Is It
Aesthetic?
When is our boredom
about a particular space aesthetic boredom and when is it simply
boredom? I am suggesting here that the reason why we can talk about, at least,
one form of aesthetic boredom about spaces is because our experience of
boredom can have as its intentional object what I call the aesthetic quality of
inhabitability. And this aesthetic quality is a quality of—i.e., a quality we
perceive in—spaces. This is why we can talk about aesthetic boredom
about spaces.
As mentioned above, I have defended somewhere else (Franco,
2019) that our aesthetic preferences for spaces
respond to our search for inhabitability. Inhabitability is what we look
for when we look for aesthetically valuable or preferable spaces. It is what we
value when we value a space aesthetically. And what we value is the quality of
the space which we experience as being responsible for affording significant
possibilities for action (i.e., activities significant for us) and for positively
enhancing the felt quality of the experience of realizing, or the
anticipation of realizing, those (or some of those) activities. ‘Significant’
possibilities ‘for us’ are possibilities that allow us to develop the life we
want to live—which means they are (spatially) significant in relation to our
personal ideal of life. Qualitatively ‘enhanced’ possibilities are experiences
whose felt quality has been increased positively, i.e., possibilities whose
realization feels better (in this space).
Thus, of two spaces, the one that enhances more or
enhances the felt quality of a greater number of activities of significance for
us would be aesthetically preferable. This space would have greater general inhabitability
for us, at least, at this moment of our life. A space that allows us to
realize more activities of significance would also be preferable even if
it does not enhance positively the felt quality of the experience of realizing
any particular activity. In other words, the very
possibility of realizing an activity can be considered the first degree of
enhancement. The aesthetically preferable café is the one where it feels better
to do what we want to do in it—or, we could equally say, even if it sounds
strange, where the space feels better as we do in it what is significant
for us. And it feels better because it allows for, and enhances qualitatively,
the experience of realizing possibilities that are significant for us (at this
moment in our life). In this case those possibilities are the ones included in
what we take to be part of the experience of having a coffee, which is,
in fact, a cluster of lived actions and passions: reading, having coffee,
seeing people, listening to music, feeling the café’s atmosphere, talking to
people, etc.
Notice that a central aspect of this aesthetic
evaluation—i.e., the evaluation of a space’s inhabitability—is the perceived
relation between the particular space we are
evaluating (if we can talk like this, as opposed to Space) and the
spaces contiguous to it. This is in agreement with the idea, suggested above,
that we evaluate Space interrupted (or filled) in different ways rather
than individual spaces, and with the idea that how our life fits in that
space is a key aspect of this evaluation. This is so because
we are constantly searching for spaces which afford significant possibilities,
and since life is continuous and always requires spaces, it means we are also
searching for significant contiguity between those possibilities. The
possibilities of the living room—and our aesthetic appreciation of it—depend on
where and how it is situated in the apartment; the possibilities of our
apartment depend on where and how it is situated in relation to other spaces in
the city; and so on. A space is aesthetically preferable if we perceive that it
allows for our life to develop continuously in a significant way, that is,
through contiguous spaces that afford significant possibilities.
Inhabitability is always inhabitability 1) for me (i.e.,
in relation to my ideal of life), 2) at this moment of my life (i.e., under the
influence of all the personal particularities that may affect my perception of
the world or my ideal of life at this very moment), and 3) in relation to
certain activities. This is what defines the framework of reference for our
evaluations. A space can be said to have general or particular
inhabitability. The latter would be greater inhabitability with
respect to a particular activity (e.g., having a coffee, reading a book,
meditating); the former with respect to a range of significant activities
(e.g., a house, a workplace, a school). Inhabitability explains not only our
preference for spaces as we commonly refer to them (this café, this office,
this apartment, etc.) but also why we choose the orientation we choose as we
occupy a space (e.g., facing the window or the interior of the café; sitting at
the front or by the aisle in a theater), the specific location within that
space (e.g., between the piano and the window), and even the bodily posture we
adopt (e.g., standing at the bar vs. sitting). All these preferences are
aimed at experiencing greater inhabitability.
Notice that repetition by itself—i.e., the repeated use
of a particular space—might not imply a reduction in the qualitative degree of
experienced inhabitability. We do return to the same park bench for lunch and
to the same café day after day, year after year. Time, however, might on the one
hand bring about changes in our ideal of life, and thus on the activities that
are significant for us; and on the other it might reveal that a space (e.g.,
our home) does not allow for the realization of certain (previously) imagined
significant possibilities or for their qualitative enhancement. This might
reduce the degree of inhabitability we might perceive in that space. To this we
can add that, if inhabitability itself—as I would suggest—triggers a
distinctive affective response, we should certainly expect a gradual reduction
in the intensity of our response as a space becomes familiar (which also means
it becomes simultaneously imbued with other emotions). On the other hand, we
can also expect that repeated exposure to the same space might increase—whether
indefinitely or provisionally—its degree of inhabitability for other reasons:
new possible activities or new manners to enhance the felt-quality of those
activities might be discovered.
I am proposing to think about aesthetic boredom about a
space we are occupying as boredom due to the lack of inhabitability of that
space. For the experience of boredom to occur, however, it would not be enough
to simply occupy such a space. Boredom requires also, at least, that the space
itself attracts sufficiently our attention and that our evaluation of that
space becomes significant within the overall meaning we may find in the situation in which we are (i.e., doing this
activity here at this very moment of my life). An elevator might be a boring
space, even an aesthetically boring space, but this boringness might
only become experientially relevant if 1) we pay attention to the elevator
space, and if 2) the boringness can be said to define the situation
in which we are (to the point of coloring or altering noticeably our general
affective state). The short period of time we usually spend in an elevator, as
well as the freedom not to pay attention to the elevator space are obstacles
for these conditions to exist. A boring library that we occupy for hours in a
row to write a paper might have a greater effect on us, both because of the
time we spend in it and because we might pay more direct attention to the space
we occupy—all of which might result in reinforcing the clash between our search
for inhabitability and the space (see section 3.2 below).
If we can talk about proper aesthetic boredom
about a space—i.e. the sort of ideal case—this might be best revealed to
us when the space not only absorbs us as fully as possible (i.e., we are
physically immersed in it and our attention is oriented towards it) and we have
not chosen it freely but also, at the same time, either 1) we are not engaged
in any other activity that requires our attention, or 2) we are forced to
realize an activity in that space which we have not chosen freely. The
former cases—i.e., not engaged in any activity that requires our attention—seem
to be a bit unusual in our everyday life. Being in a doctor’s office’s waiting
room without anything to do (no phone in our hands, no magazines to read) could
be that situation. The latter cases could be exemplified by having to attend
lectures in a boring classroom or being forced to work in a boring cubicle.
It has often been said that Edward Hopper (1882-1967)
painted well loneliness in our modern life (e.g., Jenkins, 2020; Levin, 2021). It could also be said that he
painted well the negative affect that certain spaces produce via aesthetic
boredom. Hopper’s better-known paintings highlight the significance for the
perception and evaluation of space of three particular features: the activity
we are realizing (1927, 1939), the
light (1951) and whether other humans occupy
the same space and how—in particular, their absence (1925, 1930) and the lack of human interactions
(1942, 1958, 1960) in places where we should probably expect it (such as a theater, a
café, the beach, or a gas station [1940]).[10]
These variables can alter—in fact, they reduce, in Hopper’s paintings—the
space’s degree of inhabitability. We might prefer not to sit in our favorite
café when it is empty or when we perceive a cold atmosphere (Hopper, 1942, 1958). We would not choose the interior
of a movie theater to absorb ourselves in our personal problems (Hopper, 1939). Similarly, we might prefer not to walk in the desolate streets of a
Spanish town in August during siesta time (Hooper, 1930), or
stay after hours by ourselves in an office lit by florescent tubes (Hooper, 1927). The activity, the light, and the presence and behavior of other
humans can contribute to make us feel, as we often say, ‘out of place’—or as if
we were in a ‘cold’ place (as opposed to a warm or cozy one, proper of spaces
with the quality of inhabitability).
Hopper’s paintings partially exemplify the lack of
fittingness that we should expect as casually responsible for the negative
emotion which is opposite to the emotion about the inhabitability of
spaces.[11] Common
colloquial statements such as ‘I could not be doing this in a better place’, or
‘I cannot be in a better place at this moment [i.e., doing this]’ express well
the opposite, that is, the fittingness proper of inhabitability.Whereas
the experience of inhabitability results from the fittingness between 1) the
activity we are doing as we occupy or fill that space, 2) our perception of the
space (via both sensible features and their meaning), and 3) our ideal
of life, aesthetic boredom emerges from their conflict.
Imagine you need a place to sleep while you attend a
conference. You book a room in an average road motel (in, say, the United
States). As you check in, you do not expect to find or to experience anything
new. All you hope for is to have a clean and minimally functional space. If any
hope for something better still existed, upon entering your room a strong
impression of déjà vu drowns it immediately. Despite this, you still
search for something somehow exciting (as opposed to boring):[12]
you play with the lights, open the curtains to look out of the windows (which
happen to face, one an empty parking lot and the other a dirty white wall which
is only one and a half meters away from your own window), let the light in,
bring the small armchair closer to the window and sit on it for a few minutes,
and so on. The place does seem to let you do basic things (sleep, read, revise
your talk, use the bathroom) but does not appear to have the capability to
enhance the felt quality of the experience of realizing any of them. In fact,
just being in the room seems to be affecting your mood negatively: it makes you
feel restless, and a bit angry. Noticing the pattern on the linens, the
upholstery of the chairs and the wallpaper only makes things worse. Little by
little, almost everything seems to be contributing to the impression that the
room is boring. The whole space seems to be impregnated, to be filled with
boredom; boredom emanates from everything.[13]
And yet, you cannot say you are bored. You are mainly worried about the talk
you must give the following day. Although you wished you could sit somewhere
else to prepare for it, there is no place to go. Working on your paper
distracts you but does not seem to completely isolate you from the emotional
consequences of the boringness that seems to impose itself on you.
Let us now think about an alternative case. You have
arrived in the same motel room with company in search of, among other things,
privacy to live an affair that is becoming, say, more and more sexually intense
(recall in the first case you chose the motel as a place to sleep while
you attended a conference). The same features of the motel room result now in
the perception of some unique mysteriousness, or cozy
familiarity, or anonymity, or even safe
dangerousness, all of which fit well within both the purpose of your stay
and your ideal of life (as causally relevant at this very moment in your life).
Thus, the motel room appears now as having good inhabitability. The same
features that seemed boring before are not able now to fill the space
with boringness. This might be so either because you perceive, in the
same or in other features, some additional meanings (mysteriousness,
coziness, isolation) which are exciting; or because you perceive
primarily a non-boring supra-meaning in the space (one depending on but
surpassing the meanings of individual features or objects). As a result, the
same physical features enhance now the felt quality of the experience of
realizing the activities—significant for your life—which you chose to do in
that room. In fact, later on, as you will recall your
time in that motel room, it might not appear as pleasant to the eyes (or to the
nose or ears or touch) but you may remember you felt well in it. We
usually think that this could be simply because of the association in our
memory between the room and the good things that happened in it. But it could
also be that it is because—which is what I want to suggest—you experienced a
three-sided fittingness between space, activity, and moment-in-our-life which
amounted to the experience of a good degree of inhabitability in that space.[14]
3.2. The Frustrated
Desire
Boredom is different
from “phenomenologically akin” (Elpidorou, 2018, p. 325) emotions, such as apathy, anhedonia,
and depression. Probably the most relevant difference is that boredom seems to
result from a frustrated desire, a desire that does not find the
possibility of realization. “Boredom is essentially a thwarted desire for
events, not necessarily pleasant ones” (Russell, 1930, p. 57);
“while situative boredom contains a longing for
something that is desired, existential boredom contains a longing for any
desire at all” (Svendsen, 2005, p. 42).
As to what causes this interruption, or frustration, or
unsatisfied longing, Russell (1930, pp. 56–57) explains that “[o]ne of the essentials of boredom consists in the contrast
between present circumstances and some other more agreeable circumstances which
force themselves irresistibly upon the imagination”. Elpidorou
(2018, p. 334) says that boredom “informs
us of a mismatch between what we desire and what is being offered to us” (see
also p. 325). In Svendsen (2005, p. 32)’s terms, this desire is a
“demand for meaning”: “[w]ithout such a demand for
meaning there would be no boredom”.[15]
Can we find this “thwarted desire” (Russell), this
“mismatch” (Elpidorou), this unsuccessful “demand for
meaning” (Svendsen) in our experiences about boring spaces—and, in particular, in our aesthetic boredom about
spaces? Yes, we can. I have argued (Franco, 2019) that
our search for inhabitability is always, so to speak, ongoing. It does not
require a decision or predisposition on our part. We are constantly actively
searching for inhabitability in the spaces in which we find ourselves
(regardless of whether we choose them or not) and for better inhabitability
when we have the possibility to choose freely between spaces. I take this
constant search to be the expression of the ‘desire’, the ‘demand’, we are
looking for in this case.
Our behavior, once again, is the key to observe
the presence of this desire. Very relevant in this sense is the importance we
assign to our choice of spaces even for routinary activities. Choosing a bench
in a park to have lunch or a table in a café does matter to us. We consider the
options, we often test them (by sitting for a second on that bench or at
that table), and we rectify if we think it might feel better to sit somewhere
else. We also feel upset if we return another day to the same park or café and
somebody has already taken our bench or our table. The same thing
can be said as we choose a seat at a dinner table, or at a movie theater, or
the side on which we prefer to walk in a street, or the orientation of the
chair on which we plan to read for a bit in the sun. Similarly, finding ourselves
in a new space we have not chosen usually triggers a desire to explore its
potential inhabitability: a new park appears as a potential running course and
its lake as a picnic area, a new square as the place for morning coffee, and a
new riverbank as a place for a summer evening walk. One of the reasons why we
want to go running in the new park the following morning is precisely because
we want to know how it feels to run in that park.
This desire for inhabitability is the desire that, when
frustrated, produces aesthetic boredom about spaces. The park, the square, or
the riverbank that do not reveal any inhabitability to our desire’s demand for
it can be said to be an aesthetically boring park, square, or riverbank. This
clash desire-reality does not leave us indifferent. We respond rather
negatively, i.e., with negative affect, which is what we should expect if we
are dealing with a form of boredom. Boredom is “unpleasant or undesirable”
(O’Brien, 2014, p. 237).
How exactly the phenomenology of this negative response
should be described might be a more complicated matter. In Elpidorou
(2017a) we read that “feelings of
dissatisfaction, attentional difficulties, and the perception of
meaninglessness” are distinctive of boredom. O’Brien (2014, p. 237) talks about an experience of both “weariness”, and
“restlessness”—despite “pulling in different directions, restlessness towards
movement and weariness away from it” (2014, p.
239). The restlessness could be explained by the ongoing failure of our desire
(for inhabitability) to find satisfaction, that is, by the very weariness
caused by the space we are occupying.
I am weary
with one thing and restless for another. I lack energy, interest, and patience
to attend to what is at hand; but I do have energy to burn, and I long for
something else to burn it on (O’Brien, 2014, p. 239).
The
colloquial statements we use to refer to spaces that we consider boring reflect
well this negative phenomenology in different degrees depending primarily on
the length of our experience, the strength of the perceived boringness
(the active source of boredom), the activities we are doing in them, and our
freedom (or lack thereof) to both choose the activity and to stay in or leave
the space. Notice that we usually refer to the more extreme cases—the most
negative ones—with adjectives that express pain caused by some limitation or
interruption, such as ‘cold’, ‘deserted’, ‘desolate’, or ‘oppressive’. We may say things of the sort: ‘it is painful
to walk in downtown Los Angeles on a Sunday afternoon’; ‘it is painful to sleep
in an abandoned airport hangar’; ‘it is painful to work under fluorescent
lights in a windowless and a sparsely furnished office’. A boring talk and a
boring movie are also ‘painful’ to listen to or to watch. But a painful space may
exhibit unique causal features of our pain. A boring space, unlike a boring
talk or a boring shirt, seems to exert limitations on our possibilities. A
boring space cuts, impedes, discourages, stops life,
the forward impulse of our present-moment life.[16]
In other words, unlike a place that has inhabitability, an aesthetically-boring
space is a space that we experience as not allowing our life to continue
developing—and therefore, as impeding that our ideal of life continues its
realization.[17]
This conclusion also suggests that we could distinguish
in our (negative) aesthetic evaluations of spaces two degrees regarding the
strength of our response, which might correspond to those we commonly consider boring
and painful spaces. Notice that we do not usually choose boring
spaces (we find ourselves in them) and that choosing the activity might not
change the experience of boredom about the space. However, the lack of choice
in this sense—the activity—can increase the negative effect of the experience.
The latter cases seem to be the ones that result in the experience that we
could call, more properly speaking, painful spaces. In other words,
whereas enduring the experience of an
aesthetically boring space usually implies the lack of free choice about the
space on our part, enduring the experience of a painful space implies, in
addition, the lack of free choice about the activity. A boring space becomes a
painful one—i.e., a still-more-unpleasant boring space—when the obligation to
use it in a particular way is added.
3.3.
An (Aesthetic) Emotion?
As to whether the
experience I am describing here meets the requirements to be considered an
emotion, we could submit it to an examination in search of the presence of the
features that allow us to identify any ordinary emotion, namely, 1) the
appraisal of an intentional object, 2) a distinctive phenomenology (subjective
feelings and felt bodily changes) and expression, 3) a disposition (or action
tendencies) towards its object, and 4) a particular function.[18]
That boredom is an affective state might not be very
problematic. Standard definitions of ‘boredom’ (Oxford English Dictionary, 2022a) either include explicitly such aspect or include an affective state as
explanans (e.g., ‘ennui’ in Oxford English Dictionary, 2022a). As we have seen above, Elpidorou (2017a, 2018) and
O’Brien (2014) also consider it an affective
state. Our experience and ordinary language seem to indicate it too.
But which type of affective state is boredom? According
to O’Brien (2014, p. 238) boredom is “not a raw
feeling” and “not quite an emotion”; “[i]t is closer
to a mood than to an emotion”. Svendsen (2005, p. 14)
also considers it a mood, at least the state of being bored, the “nameless,
shapeless, object-less boredom” (see also p. 93). Whereas “situative
boredom” is “often an emotion”, “existential boredom is always a mood” (Svendsen,
2005, p. 111). For Russell (1930, p. 56), “[b]oredom would seem to be a
distinctively human emotion”. Elpidorou (2017a) says there is “strong evidence” to consider
boredom “an emotion in its own right” if we follow the research done by Van
Tilburg and Igou (2012). As we saw above, Elpidorou (2017a) seems
to be referring to what he calls the “state of boredom” as opposed to “the
personality trait of boredom”. Elpidorou (2018) has also defended that boredom has all the
distinctive features (‘components’) of the ‘component processes account of
emotions’ proposed by Scherer (1984).
Insofar as we are talking of boredom about something,
or talking about something that causes boredom, we may already be
taking a position in the mood-vs.-emotion debate. It is a common view
that, unlike emotions, which have an “intentional object” (Svendsen, 2005, p. 110), moods are not about
“determinate objects” (e.g., Sizer, 2000, p.
747)—they are “objectless” (Svendsen, 2005, p. 110).
And even if it could be argued that moods can be about something, it seems
difficult to defend that they can be about “determinate objects” or that they
occur only in the presence of their object—as it is the case we are studying
(i.e., boredom about spaces). We feel or experience boredom about a particular
space as we occupy and fill it. The fact that we are talking about aesthetic
boredom also supports the view that we may be dealing with an emotion—at
least, insofar as ‘aesthetic’ here implies direction towards some (aesthetic)
object, and the very idea of the existence of ‘aesthetic moods’ seems itself
problematic.
On the other hand, given the nature of spaces qua objects,
it seems plausible to say that boredom (the emotion) about a particular space
might either affect or be a cause of the general ‘shapeless objectless’ boredom
that we can identify as a mood (see, e.g., Parreno, 2019). This is, however, something, that we can probably say of most
ordinary emotions—e.g., the joy about specific objects or experiences might
contribute to generate a joyful mood. Aesthetic boredom about spaces might,
in any case, exert a greater causal power to produce moods than emotions about
other objects. This is so because of its capability to intervene in
(i.e., stop, interrupt, in the case of aesthetic boredom) the continuous
development of our life.
3.3.1. The
Intentional Object: An Aesthetic Quality
When we occupy—or fill,
with our presence—spaces we may experience boredom about other things (not
space) or about other perceived qualities (not inhabitability). We may find
boring certain visual features in an architectonic structure (e.g., the colors
of the walls of a room), or the design of the furniture, or the shapes and
arrangement of the different rooms in an apartment. These experiences would not
qualify as boredom, or aesthetic boredom, about spaces.
There might be several reasons why we might perceive
specific objects or sensible qualities as boring, e.g., monotony, familiarity,
regularity, conventionality (e.g., Toohey, 2011). I
mentioned above that we could talk about a sort of boredom that takes place
only at the level of sensible perception. Shinkle (2004) has talked about “perceptual boredom” (e.g., pp. 168, 175), and given
as an example the experience of seeing the photographs of Denver by Robert
Adams in What We Bought: The New World (1970-74) (2009). Shinkle (2004, p. 177)
describes this perceptual boredom like this:
[T]he
stifling, characterless interiors of suburban tract homes quash the activity of
the eye, leaving it to slide aimlessly across bare white walls or terminate
pointlessly in empty corners. Shot in the Denver metropolitan area, the
landscapes in this series invoke the same kind of perceptual inertia: rather
than acting as an enticement to the look, the horizon serves only to separate a
bland, undifferentiated ground plane from a similarly featureless sky. Adams
pictures the American West as a field of manufactured desires, where ideals of
freedom are lived out in cookie-cutter fashion in endless rows of tract
housing. The two-dimensionality of the American dream is actualized in the
images themselves, in the way that they confine the gaze within a narrow wedge
of space and time.
Another example Shinkle (2004, p. 177) provides is the interiors
we can find in Lynn Cohen’s Occupied Territory (Cohen et al., 1987): “[t]he eerie silence of these images gives the environments the
feeling of archaeological relics rather than living—or livable—spaces”.
Notice that in both descriptions, perceptual boredom
reveals the (lack of) livability of the space—something which might
share features with my idea of inhabitability. The lack of “enticement to the
look” shows a “stifling” space which “confine[s] the gaze within a narrow wedge
of space and time”. It seems, then, that the experience described in this case
is not just simply boredom about visual or sensible features. Perceptual
boredom seems to be understood by Shinkle as related
to, but not being only about, sensible perceptions—either because the
perception itself is only partial cause, or because the effect is felt beyond
the perception.
If we place this in the context of the constitutive
structure of emotions, of which a central component is an evaluative perception
of its object, it could imply that boredom (the emotion) about spaces requires perceptual
boredom. The latter could be the evaluative perception which triggers the
corresponding emotion (in the same way that perceiving dangerousness when we
see a tiger results in fear). But if this only means that perceptual boredom is
one of the causal links of (the emotion of) boredom, it looks like we have not
made much progress.
The difference between the experience of simple boredom
about a space and aesthetic boredom about that space is a subtle one. We can
think of it as parallel to the difference between perceiving a space and
aesthetically appreciating a space. Whereas, as I have suggested above,
the former is a perception of possibilities regarding what and how I
can do in that space, the latter would be a perception of the space’s
capability to afford significant activities and to enhance (qualitatively) the
felt experience of realizing those activities in that space (i.e., what I have
called the aesthetic quality of inhabitability). The clash of my desire for
inhabitability against the lack of the first type of possibilities would be
responsible for boredom about the space; the clash between my desire and
the lack of possibilities of the second type would be responsible for aesthetic
boredom about the space. Notice that without this clash, we may be forced to
talk simply about a lack of perceived possibilities—which might result
simply in indifference.[19]
But if boredom is an emotion, it requires more than a perception: it requires
an evaluative perception. A frustrated desire of the sort outlined above would
include this type of evaluative perception.
Let us try to narrow things a bit more. A space may
appear as boring because it affords zero significant possibilities. Our
everyday evaluations of spaces—as unconscious, distracted, and quick as these
evaluations might be—indicate, however, that the clash between our
desire and those possibilities has more precise features: it is a clash that
occurs in me and at this very moment of my life. This means that
I may not see any significant possibilities in this space at this very
moment in my life. Or that I may see some significant possibilities to
do (i.e., for actions)—and, thus, the space would appear as less boring—but
I may not see yet any possibilities regarding its experience-enhancing capabilities
(i.e., the space may not improve the felt quality of the experience of
realizing those possibilities). Such a space would not be a boring space (in
the general sense), but it would be an aesthetically boring space.
3.3.2. Phenomenology
In practice, it might be
difficult to distinguish the phenomenology of our experience of (only) boredom
from that of our experience of aesthetic boredom (about a space). This might be
due, in part, to the fact that a zero-possibilities space is also a non-enhancing
(possibilities) space (or a space with no enhancing capability). A boring space
is usually also an aesthetically boring space—but, as we have seen, not
necessarily vice versa. Another reason for the difficulty to distinguish
both phenomenologies might have to do
with the fact that we are constantly either searching for the aesthetic value
of the spaces we occupy or choosing spaces (for our daily activities) that are
aesthetically preferable. This means that, as we ponder options about where
to do something, we do not usually take into consideration spaces that we
already know are boring. This is so because our daily preferences for spaces
usually have the form of finding the appropriate space for a particular task.
If the task cannot be done, the space is not even among the options we
consider. If we are thinking about a space to do what we usually do in a café—i.e.,
all that that can fit within the café experience (i.e., to read, to
write, to be among people, to listen to music, to immerse ourselves in the
noise of the café, to have a coffee, etc.)—we do not usually doubt between
going to a clothing store or to the 19th-century café in the main
square, or between a boring café and a non-boring café.
As said above, this means that our experience of boring
spaces is usually of spaces we do not choose; spaces in which we may find
ourselves and which we cannot leave, at least not immediately. Any waiting
space (waiting area in a doctor’s office, airport, business), or any space in
which we are transported (elevator, plane, train, etc.) and through which we
are transported (e.g., our commuting route) meet these conditions. A hospital
room, a motel room, a prison cell are also of this kind. Considering all this,
that is, the conditions under which we experience aesthetic boredom, its
distinctive phenomenology seems to correspond mainly to the experience of the
frustrated desire described above plus, in this case, its directedness (more or less conscious) toward a precise object: the
(inexistent) inhabitability of the space. Recall that, according to O’Brien
“weariness” and “restlessness” define this experience (2014, p. 239). The weariness is “more mental than physical”—something closer
to being “mentally exhausted” (2014, p. 240). But restlessness, the
nervous agitation proper of boredom (‘in boredom, there is no rest for the
weary’), is also central (and, as O’Brien [2014] puts
it, distinguishes boredom from languor, listlessness, or torpor).
3.3.3. Disposition
and Function
Elpidorou (2018, p. 340)
considers it a “recent trend” to take boredom “to be an emotional or affective
state that serves a purpose in our everyday lives”. This is a bit surprising,
given the consensus that emotions do have a function, that is, that they serve
a purpose. “Emotions and feelings […] have a useful function” (Fridja, 1986, p. 372); “[e]motions serve
something, and presumably they serve it well” (1986, p. 475). About this function, Elpidorou
(2018, p. 326) has argued that, in brief,
“boredom promotes movement; movement is essential to well-being; ergo, boredom
promotes well-being”.
First of all, boredom is a
negative emotion. “The state of boredom is unpleasant. Boredom is a form of
dissatisfaction and discontent” (O’Brien, 2014, p. 241);
“Boredom in the ordinary sense is disturbing, unpleasant and unbearable”
(Heidegger, 1995, p. 158). Negative emotions, by
definition, dispose us to go away from their intentional object, in this case,
from boring spaces. It is proper of the state of boredom that “one wishes to do
something else” (Elpidorou, 2017a); “it [the boring book] brings us into an
attunement that we would like to see suppressed” (Heidegger, 1995, p. 87). In this sense, we can expect
aesthetic boredom to have a beneficial function.
As mentioned above, we do not usually choose purposefully
either boring or aesthetically boring spaces. We find ourselves in them. And
when we find ourselves in them, we wish to be somewhere else. The time we spend
in an aesthetically boring space is, rather than time wasted (as we usually put
it), space wasted if we consider our ongoing search for better quality
of life.[20]
Each time we can choose among several spaces to do something, we have in our
hands the possibility of improving the quality of our life (while we do that
activity) by improving (via the space) the felt quality of what we are
planning to do. In other words, each choice can bring our life closer to the
realization of our ideal of life. Choosing the aesthetically exciting (as
opposed to boring) café, the aesthetically exciting table at the café, the
aesthetically exciting place or orientation at the table, means taking
advantage of unique and unrepeatable opportunities to enhance the felt quality
of—i.e., the experience of realizing—the activities we are doing. Aesthetic
boredom about spaces, thus, alerts us of the danger of wasting space and
disposes us to avoid placing our life in spaces that either interrupt it (i.e.,
do not allow for its development) or that do not enhance it qualitatively.[21]
4. Conclusions
I have tried to explain
what we mean when we say in our everyday life that certain built spaces are ‘boring’.
I have proposed that this can be an aesthetic judgement and that, in such
cases, we can talk about aesthetic boredom about spaces. As an
emotion, aesthetic boredom is the corresponding negative emotion to what might
be called our aesthetic excitement about a space. Whereas this positive
affective response would be about the aesthetic quality of inhabitability, the negative one
(aesthetic boredom) would be about its absence. In other words, unlike (simple)
boredom about a space, aesthetic boredom would be boredom due to the
absence of the aesthetic quality of inhabitability in the space we are
occupying. (Inhabitability is the quality of a space which we experience as
being responsible for 1) creating possibilities significant for us regarding
what we can do and how we can do it in that space, and for 2) enhancing
(qualitatively) the experience of realizing those possibilities).
Since, as it is commonly understood, boredom, unlike
indifference, involves a frustrated desire, I have argued that, in this case,
this is the desire that we experience in our constant search for inhabitability in any space in which we find
ourselves, and for greater inhabitability when we can choose between spaces.
The significance of the frustration of this desire for our life explains the
considerable strength of our (negative) response to boring spaces. It is a
response, not simply to not encountering significant possibilities to do and to
enhance their felt quality (i.e., to the absence of inhabitability), but
rather, to realizing that there are none where there should be some (for our life to continue well). Aesthetically boring spaces deny inhabitability. And in this sense, they are spaces which interrupt the progress of our individual life in an important sense: they
interrupt our desire and continuous search for spaces that allow for a better
realization of our ideal of life. And by doing this they impede the continuous increase of the quality of our life.
References
Adams, R. (2009). What We Bought:
The New World: Scenes from the Denver Metropolitan Area 1970–1974. Yale
University Art Gallery.
Augé, M.
(1995). Non-places: Introduction to an Anthropology of Supermodernity. Verso.
Böhme,
G. (1993). Atmosphere as the Fundamental Concept of a New Aesthetics. Thesis
Eleven, 36(1), 113–126. https://doi.org/10.1177/072551369303600107
Böhme, G.
(2017a). The Aesthetics of Atmospheres. Routledge.
Böhme, G.
(2017b). The Ecstasies of Things:
Ontology and Aesthetics of Thingness. In Atmospheric Architectures: The Aesthetics
of Felt Spaces (pp. 37–54). Bloomsbury.
Cohen, L.,
Ewing, W. A., Byrne, D., and Mellor, D. (1987). Occupied Territory.
Aperture Foundation.
Cova, F., and
Deonna, J. A. (2014). Being Moved. Philosophical Studies, 169(3),
447–466. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0192-9
https://doi.org/10.1177/1754073909345544
De Matteis, F. (2021). Affective Spaces: Architecture and the Living Body.
Routledge.
Doehlemann, M. (1991). Langeweile? Deutung eines verbreiteten
Phänomens. Suhrkamp.
Dundon,
R. (2016, November 1). Beautifully Boring Pictures of Typical
American Architecture. Medium. https://timeline.com/photos-beautifully-boring-architecture-808e902555af
Elpidorou, A. (2017a). Boredom in Art. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 40,
E359. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X17001674
Elpidorou, A. (2017b) The Bored Mind Is a Guiding Mind: Toward a Regulatory Theory
of Boredom. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(3),
455–484. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9515-1
Elpidorou, A. (2018). The Good of Boredom. Philosophical Psychology, 31(3),
323–351. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2017.1346240
Franco, A.
(2019). Our Everyday Aesthetic Evaluations of Architecture. The British
Journal of Aesthetics, 59(4), 393–412. https://doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayz018
Fridja
N. H. (1986). The Emotions. Cambridge University Press.
Gamsby,
P. (2019). Boredom: Emptiness in the Modern World. In M. H. Jacobsen (Ed.), Emotions,
Everyday Life and Sociology (pp. 209–224). Routledge.
Gamsby, P. (2022). Henri Lefebvre, Boredom,
and Everyday Life. Lexington Books/Fortress Academic.
Griffero, T. (2019). Is There Such a Thing as an ‘Atmospheric Turn’? Instead of
an Introduction. In T. Griffero, and M. Tedeschini (Eds.), Atmosphere and Aesthetics: A Plural
Perspective (pp. 11–62). Springer.
Hopper, E.
(1925). House by the Railroad [Painting]. Museum of Modern Art, New York, NY, United States. https://www.moma.org/collection/works/78330
Hopper, E.
(1927). Automat [Painting]. Des Moines Art Center, Des
Moines, IA, United States. https://emuseum.desmoinesartcenter.org/objects/41752/automat?ctx=00d51a37087419f90ef8abcb45112c31e2e491cf&idx=1
Hopper, E.
(1930). Early Sunday Morning [Painting]. Whitney Museum of American Art,
New York, NY, United States. https://whitney.org/collection/works/46345
Hopper, E.
(1939). New York Movie [Painting]. Museum of Modern Art, New York,
NY, United States. https://www.moma.org/collection/works/79616
Hopper, E. (1940). Gas [Painting].
Museum of Modern Art, New York, NY,
United States. https://www.moma.org/collection/works/80000
Hopper, E.
(1942). Nighthawks [Painting]. The Art Institute of Chicago, Chicago,
IL, United States. https://www.artic.edu/artworks/111628/nighthawks
Hopper, E.
(1951). Rooms by the Sea [Painting]. Yale University Art Gallery,
New Haven, CT, United States. https://artgallery.yale.edu/collections/objects/52939
Hopper, E.
(1958). Sunlight in a Cafeteria [Painting]. Yale University Art Gallery,
New Haven, CT, United States. https://artgallery.yale.edu/collections/objects/52642
Hopper, E.
(1960). People in the Sun [Painting]. Smithsonian American Art
Museum, Washington, DC, United States. https://americanart.si.edu/artwork/people-sun-10762
Jenkins, D.
(2020). Loneliness, Art and the City. Contemporary Aesthetics, 8
(Urban Aesthetics). https://contempaesthetics.org/2020/07/16/loneliness-art-and-the-city/
Levin, G.
(2021). Edward Hopper’s Loneliness. Social Research: An International
Quarterly, 88(3), 747–770. https://doi.org/10.1353/sor.2021.0038
McKeough, T.
(2022, March 29). The Best Room in Your Home? It Could Be the Laundry Room. The New York Times. https://www.nytimes.com/2022/03/29/realestate/laundry-room-space.html
Michaels, W.
B. (2021). Dumb and Boring. In P. Preissner, Kind of Boring:
Canonical Work and Other Visible Things Meant to Be Viewed as Architecture (pp.
163–167). Actar.
Mihalache, A. (2020). Musings on Boredom, Midcentury Architecture, and Public Spaces.
The Plan Journal, 5(1), 119–138. https://doi.org/10.15274/tpj.2020.05.01.11
O’Brien, W.
(2014). Boredom. Analysis, 74(2), 236–244. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anu041
Oxford English
Dictionary (2022a). Boredom, n. OED Online. Oxford University Press.
Oxford English Dictionary (2022b).
Ennui, n. OED Online. Oxford University Press.
Oxford English
Dictionary (2022c). Boring, adj.2. OED Online. Oxford University Press.
Parreno, C. (2019). A Laboratory for Boredom. Journal of Architectural
Education, 73(1), 107–109. https://doi.org/10.1080/10464883.2019.1560818
Parreno, C. (2021). Boredom, Architecture, and Spatial Experience. Bloomsbury
Visual Arts.
Petty, J.
(2016). The London Spikes Controversy: Homelessness, Urban Securitisation
and the Question of “Hostile Architecture.” International Journal for Crime,
Justice and Social Democracy, 5(1), 67–81. https://doi.org/10.5204/ijcjsd.v5i1.286
Preissner, P. (2021a). Kind of Boring: Canonical Work and Other Visible Things
Meant to Be Viewed as Architecture. Actar.
Preissner, P. (2021b). Kind of Boring. In Kind of Boring: Canonical Work and Other
Visible Things Meant to Be Viewed as Architecture (pp. 168–173). Actar.
Russell, B.
(1930). The Conquest of Happiness. Horace Liveright.
Schmitz, H. (1965). System der Philosophie:
Band 2. Teil 1: Der Leib. Bouvier.
Schmitz, H. (1969). System der Philosophie:
Band 3. Teil 2: Der Gefühlsraum. Bouvier.
Shinkle, E. (2004). Boredom, Repetition, Inertia: Contemporary Photography and
the Aesthetics of the Banal. Mosaic (Winnipeg), 37(4), 165–184.
Svendsen, L.
(2005). A Philosophy of Boredom. Reaktion Books.
Teroni,
F. (2007). Emotions and Formal Object. Dialéctica,
61(3), 395–415.
Toohey, P.
(2011). Boredom: A Lively History. Yale University Press.
Van
Tilburg, W. A., and Igou, E. R. (2012). On Boredom: Lack of Challenge and Meaning
as Distinct Boredom Experiences. Motivation and Emotion, 36(2),
181–194. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-011-9234-9
Ward, M. (2012,
April 10). Boring Urban Landscapes. SB129.
https://sb129.com/2012/04/10/boring-urban-landscapes/
[1] The direct focus on
the everydayness of the individual user’s experience of architecture
distinguishes this paper from other significant studies on architecture that
have taken into account boredom. The latter have usually
taken boredom to be a (collective) mood proper of a historical period which has
been (at least partially) created by architecture or that has affected the
practice of architecture (e.g., Gamsby, 2019, 2022; Mihalache,
2020; Parreno, 2019, 2021; Preissner, 2021a, 2021b). Mihalache (2020, p. 135), for example, concludes his study on boredom
and midcentury architecture thus: “At its worst, boredom is the malaise of the
modern individual confronted with both excess and dearth. At its best, it
offers an unexpected potential for contemplation, reflection, and critical
judgment” (cf. “Conclusion” in Gamsby, 2019, p. 222). The
analysis of the individual experience and, in
particular, the extent to which it might be an aesthetic experience
reduces more its scholarly company (even if we also take into account studies
on philosophy of architecture or everyday aesthetics). As it will be clearer
throughout the paper, adopting this approach—especially the analysis of the
subject’s unique experience itself—results in some other significant
differences with respect to the standard ways of talking about
architecture: one is that architecture, rather than qua created physical
object which is evaluated visually, appears primarily qua created space
which is evaluated doing something in it and from the perception of visual
and non-visual qualities; another is that our experience, far from being
determined by the architectonic structure, is the result of creative encounters
with it (cf. Borden, 2014).
[2] This type of object
is what philosophers have called the formal object of an emotion, that
is the object shared by all instances of an emotion (Teroni,
2007).
[3] This does not mean
that we cannot also talk about the effect of boredom as a mood—or a “condition”
or a “malady” (Parreno, 2021, p. 2)—which might both condition our perception of
architecture and be proper of our time, as Parreno (2021) has defended.
[4] Svendsen claims to
be following a typology by Doehlemann (1991, pp. 22–23): “I
prefer Martin Doehlemann’s typology, which
distinguishes between four types of boredom: situative
boredom, as when one is waiting for someone, is listening to a lecture or
taking the train; the boredom of satiety, when one gets too much of the same
thing and everything becomes banal; existential boredom, where the soul is
without content and the world is in neutral; and creative boredom, which is not
so much characterized by its content as its result: that one is forced to do
something new” (2005, pp. 41–42). Among other classifications of boredom based on its
content, particularly influential on discussions on boredom and architecture
has been the one offered by Heidegger (1995) which is ordered “with respect to depth” (p. 130)
(from less to more): ‘becoming bored by something’, ‘being bored with something’,
and ‘profound boredom’. As examples of the ‘something’ of the first experience,
Heidegger gives a book and a railway station; and as example of the second type
of experience, he mentions the case of someone who, after a “pleasant” evening,
realizes later on that he “was bored with the evening”
(p. 109). “Profound boredom” is a mood, a “fundamental attunement” (p. 132),
that gives us access to the “essence of time” (p. 133) and opens the “authentic
possibility of its [our] existence” (p. 153). Among the classifications not
strictly based on the content of the experience, Gamsby
(2019)’s has also had an
influence on discussions on architecture and boredom. He talks about three
“views” of boredom depending on their historical presence or significance:
“ordinary” boredom which is “equated with individual emptiness” (and also
“easily remedied and ultimately unworthy of serious attention”) (p. 210); the
“ahistorical” view takes boredom to be a “universal experience” (p. 210); and the
view that “takes boredom to be an historically specific phenomenon, one that is
inextricably tied to modern life” (p. 211). Thus put, the experience of boredom
I am dealing with here, would fall within the first type studied by Heidegger
and, somehow, under the first two views mentioned by Gamsby.
[5] As an object,
however, the distinctiveness of space can make the experience also closer to an
emotional response to a situation (rather than to ‘something specific’).
Parreno (2019, p. 108) refers to a case of boredom supposedly
caused by continuous living in a monotonous confined space (a room) as being
“triggered by the environment”.
[6] See a discussion of cases in which the
“boring” cannot be said to cause boredom in Heidegger (1995, p. 86). Notice
that we also commonly say that the non-boring causes boredom if we are exposed
to it repeatedly. “Much boredom derives from repetition. I am often bored, for
example, when I go to museums and galleries and only find pale imitations of works I have seen already far too many times. I am bored
when I hear a lecture for the fourth time, and I am bored when I give a lecture
for the fourth time” (2005, p. 41). Although Svendsen uses ‘being bored’, our experience indicates
that the repetition itself might be ‘boring’ but we
may not experience boredom as such.
[7] In Heidegger’s
terms, “[t]he landscape is not itself melancholy, but merely attunes us in such
a way, causes this attunement in us. And similarly
with the ‘boring book’” (1995, p. 85).
[8] Cf.: “The heresy
that architectural value resides in the image or concept of a building rather
than in its creation, experience and use has been around since the rise of
printing and the subsequent diffusion of treatises by Palladio and other
architects” (Saint, 2014, p. 35).
[9] Atmospheres,
according to Böhme, are “spaces insofar as they are
‘tinctured’ through the presence of things, of persons or environmental constellations”
(1993, p. 121); “it
[atmosphere] is the felt presence of something or someone in space” (Böhme, 2017a, p. 33); “I would call atmosphere the sphere of the felt
bodily presence” (Böhme, 2017b, p. 69). Böhme explains this “presence” with his concept of ‘ecstasies’.
“Forms of presence […] are modes in which a thing characteristically steps out
of itself. I call these ecstasies” (2017b, p. 46). Instead of thinking of blueness as something
the cup has, Böhme says, “[t]he blueness of
the cup […] can be thought […] as the way, or better, a way, in which the cup
is present in space and makes its presence perceptible. The blueness of the cup
is then thought of […] as something which radiates out to the environment of
the cup, colouring or ‘tincturing’ in a certain way
this environment” (1993, p. 121). In some occasions, Böhme says atmospheres “fill” spaces: “Atmospheres fill
spaces; they emanate from things, constellations of things and persons” (2017a, p. 26). This is
consistent with the idea I have suggested above that we should think about
space, the space we perceive, as content rather than container. Notice,
on the other hand, that although Böhme (1993) places atmospheres
at the centre of a ‘new aesthetics’, we should
understand ‘aesthetics’ here, as Griffero (2019) has put it, as a
general theory of perception (as conceived under the prism of Schmitz’s new phenomenology
[1965, 1969]). Unlike the
concept of inhabitability, the concept of atmosphere by itself does not
isolate what we take to be the aesthetic quality of a space.
[10] A crowded café and
an empty café are different spaces (cf. De Matteis, 2021). The possibilities
are different. Their meanings can also be different—and, thus, their felt
quality. A crowded café in which people are interacting and a crowded café in
which nobody is interacting may also have quite different meanings. And
different meaning means different perceived capability to enhance the felt
experience of what we want to do in the café.
[11] Although I am not
arguing directly in this paper for the existence of the emotion of
inhabitability, we can understand it, as I have suggested above, as the
opposite of—i.e., the positive side of—the emotion I call here aesthetic
boredom.
[13] Cf. Heidegger (1995, p. 92): “It
[boredom] does not merely relate to the particular thing that is boring us, but
settles over several things, over other things: everything becomes boring”.
[14] The lack of this
three-sided fittingness is, I would say, what is behind Parreno
(2019, p. 108)’s “boredom
surfaces as a suspended synchronization between inhabitants and architecture”.
[15] “[B]oredom is inhuman because it robs human life of meaning, or
possibly it is an expression of the fact that such a meaning is absent”
(Svendsen, 2005, p. 33); “boredom
is not a question of work or freedom but of meaning” (Svendsen, 2005, p. 35); “The world
becomes boring when everything is transparent” (Svendsen, 2005, p. 38).
[16] Cf. Heidegger (1995, p. 87): “that
which bores, which is boring, is that which holds us in limbo and yet leaves
us empty”. Being “held in limbo” means that “we are given over to it [the
boring], yet not taken by it”, which is what it means to say that the “boring”
is “wearisome” according to Heidegger (1995, p. 86). “Being left empty” means, in the case of the
boring railway station, that “[w]hat is at hand (the station) does not offer
that which we expect of it in the particular situation.
The station accordingly does not fulfill our expectation of it” (1995, pp.103–104).
[17] Notice that under
the view I am presenting here the so-called ‘hostile architecture’ (e.g.,
Petty, 2016) would refer properly
speaking, rather than to spaces, to certain architectonic modifications,
usually of the urban built environment, aimed at limiting certain possibilities
(e.g., skating, sitting, putting up a tent). This would not be, however, enough
to talk about ‘hostile spaces’, and, therefore, of hostile architecture proper.
‘Hostile spaces’ could be an appropriate way of referring to boring spaces.
[18] These criteria are
quite similar to the five criteria which, according to Cova and Deonna (2014, p. 449) constitute
“a good indication that we are dealing with a distinct emotion” (for a defense
of these criteria, see Deonna and Scherer, 2010).
[19] “We straightway
take ‘boring’ as meaning wearisome, tedious, which is not to say
indifferent” (Heidegger, 1995, p. 86).
[20] This idea of ‘wasted
space’ is somehow similar to Augé (1995)’s view of ‘non-place’: “If a place can be defined as relational,
historical and concerned with identity, then a space which cannot be defined as
relational, or historical, or concerned with identity will be a non-place” (pp.
77–78). The latter seem to be spaces where, according to my view, few people
would find inhabitability. But we should not forget that the very
personal character of this quality can make it always possible for someone to
find it in almost any space.
[21] Preissner
(2021b) and Michaels (2021) have explicitly
defended a ‘boring’ or ‘dumb’ architecture. But they do this after redefining ‘boring’
(and ‘dumb’) in a manner that would not quite fall within what in this paper
has been considered such. Preissner (2021b, p. 168) sees
boring architecture as opposed to architecture that exists “in the world of
distinction and efforts to constantly capture our attention (through our eyes)”,
something which “tend[s] to make us unfree”. As Preissner
(2021b, p. 169) sees it
“[b]oring things open the world up. […] Boring and
dull things are empty. However, it is this void that allows for things which
are normal, anonymous, and quotidian to become weird and strange and make space
for the imagination. It’s a free space in all the ways that interesting things
are a closed room” (cf. Parreno [2021, p. 104]: “the
boredom of Los Angeles […] nurtur[es] a field of
possibilities and experimentation”; and Mihalache, 2020). Similarly,
Michaels (2021, p. 164)
acknowledges that although “boring means what it usually does (not
interesting)”, “not interesting” does not mean what it usually does: “not
interesting means not that you can’t be interested in it but that it doesn’t
demand your interest”. And “dumb”—as in “aesthetically dumb”—“means
not only not telling you what to do but also not caring what you do”.
Aesthetically dumb architecture “leaves us room to think for ourselves”
(Michaels, 2021, p. 166);
“aesthetically dumb architecture not only leaves you alone but must be
understood as leaving you alone” (Michaels, 2021, p. 165). Thus understood, ‘boring’ or ‘dumb’
architecture would not fall, under the view presented in this paper, as
architecture that conveys boringness. Another question is whether, as Preissner and Michaels defend, such architecture is
desirable. Seeing significant possibilities in a space is, in fact, part of our
search for inhabitability, and it does require the active (and free) engagement
of the imagination. However, any created space, opens and limits possibilities.
We cannot think of a created space that only opens possibilities. On the other
hand, it seems that a good part of the attention a space attracts—as unfocused
and diffused as it might be in our everyday life--has to do with the
possibilities we (individually, personally) see in it. These possibilities, in
turn, are limited by the power of our imagination which is itself conditioned
by the space we perceive: we cannot easily imagine possibilities without experiencing
the space whose possibilities we are imagining. Thus, saying that a ‘boring’
space lets us be free by not attracting our attention might make the freedom
involved irrelevant, freedom that cannot be realized.